Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W1520068536> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 66 of
66
with 100 items per page.
- W1520068536 startingPage "52" @default.
- W1520068536 abstract "If you suggest some fresh and more ingenious reason for doubting that the author meant what he said, or that what he said had any truth content of the remotest kind, you win ten points by the rules of the modern critical game; you lose ten points if you suggest he said it because he meant it, and twenty if you suggest he said it because it was true. --George Watson, Times Literary Supplement The problem of interpretation, central to literary theory and critical practice, is one of the most difficult on anybody's research agenda. As if to illustrate the point, much like professional politicians, philosophers and literary scholars who write on interpretation appear to agree only to disagree. While there have always existed schools of interpretation, today's proliferation of positions, oppositions, suppositions, presuppositions, and propositions on the matter seems to flow from the centrality of the notion of text in critical theory and practice, and the corresponding marginalization of the concept of work. Arguing for a categorical distinction between texts and works, this paper points to an alternative to such textualism professed most frequently, though not exclusively, by scholars of poststructuralist persuasion. With this goal in mind, it discusses in turn the distinction between works and texts, the role of intentions in interpretation, the distinction between work interpretations and textual readings, and the role of cognition in literary research. From Text to Work. What is a work of art? Is it identical with its structure (text)? If not, what is the relationship between the work and its structure? What elements other than textual may be constitutive of an artwork's identity? What is the interpretive relevance, if any, of the artist's intentions in the creation of the work? The merit of various theories of interpretation can be gauged roughly by their success in handling these questions while adhering to commonsensical critical intuitions and common critical practice. Elsewhere I have defended at length the view that a work of art is an structure executed by the artist in a particular art-historical context. (1) While not highly regarded in literary theory, this view has traditionally underwritten our interpretive and critical practice, becoming in recent years the subject of intense study by philosophers in analytic aesthetics. (2) One thing that this new paradigm makes clear is that works of art, and thus works of literature, are not equivalent to their structures (or texts) when considered from the point of view of identity. Building on this interdisciplinary research, I would like to focus on the interpretive aspects of this work-text nonequivalence. A good way to start may be to examine what features of a work of art are relevant to its appreciation. Despite conclusive refutations (see below), a sizeable body of criticism continues to profess that, interpretively speaking, a work of art is equivalent to its structure. On this view a work of art, together with all its and artistic features, is not distinct from the physical entity (the text) that we get at by means of purely sensory perception. I will apply the label of aesthetic structuralism to this family of views that holds that the evidence for interpretation rests solely on the evidence of the senses. For the structuralist, even though artworks may indeed have features other than directly perceptible ones, which can even be of considerable historical or biographical interest, such properties have no bearing on these works' or artistic properties. Such or artistic properties are judged to be independent, for example, of the work's history of creation, including the significant subset of this history bracketed off by the artist's executive intentions. The inclusion of work-related facts, whether culled from the artist's life or from the history of the work's composition, would on such a view take us outside the perceived art-ifact, contrary to the structuralist sine qua non. …" @default.
- W1520068536 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W1520068536 creator A5072041028 @default.
- W1520068536 date "2005-01-01" @default.
- W1520068536 modified "2023-10-01" @default.
- W1520068536 title "Is There a Work in This Classroom? Interpretations, Textual Readings, and American Fiction" @default.
- W1520068536 hasPublicationYear "2005" @default.
- W1520068536 type Work @default.
- W1520068536 sameAs 1520068536 @default.
- W1520068536 citedByCount "0" @default.
- W1520068536 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W1520068536 hasAuthorship W1520068536A5072041028 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C124952713 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C142362112 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C144024400 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C204321447 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C21190884 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C2776608531 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C2781310500 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C41008148 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C41895202 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConcept C527412718 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C111472728 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C124952713 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C138885662 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C142362112 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C144024400 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C204321447 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C21190884 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C2776608531 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C2781310500 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C41008148 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C41895202 @default.
- W1520068536 hasConceptScore W1520068536C527412718 @default.
- W1520068536 hasIssue "1" @default.
- W1520068536 hasLocation W15200685361 @default.
- W1520068536 hasOpenAccess W1520068536 @default.
- W1520068536 hasPrimaryLocation W15200685361 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W140013099 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W1983337846 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2030584258 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2078438408 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2086409495 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2087678737 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2130748770 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2143231620 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2264224309 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2324697833 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2436175051 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2480641264 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W2504816051 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W3007155668 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W3137865430 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W317528296 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W337346212 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W36802679 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W433602289 @default.
- W1520068536 hasRelatedWork W862705537 @default.
- W1520068536 hasVolume "32" @default.
- W1520068536 isParatext "false" @default.
- W1520068536 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W1520068536 magId "1520068536" @default.
- W1520068536 workType "article" @default.