Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W1568787489> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 55 of
55
with 100 items per page.
- W1568787489 abstract "Contract has been conceptualized as a species of promise. Treating contractual promise as a kind of promise highlights certain important aspects of contracting, but it also obscures essential differences between legally binding and everyday, or what I will call promises. The moral character of a private promise depends on the fact that it is not only freely made but also freely kept. Most contractual promises are not intended to have and (by definition) do not have this voluntary character. A promisor essentially opts out of the private practice of promising when she assigns to a third party the authority to coerce performance of her promise.In making a private promise, a promisor creates a sufficient reason to perform the content of her promise: the very fact of her promise. To the extent she creates a second sufficient reason - liability in the case of breach - the first reason does no work, or, there is no way for the independent sufficiency of the first reason to manifest itself objectively. Similarly, in being made a private promise, a promisee is given ground for belief that the promisor will perform: again, the fact of promise. To the extent the promisee is independently assured of performance, she cannot objectively rely on the fact of promise alone. The act of contracting removes one from the moral world of private promise.Some contractual promises co-exist with private promises of the same content. But their co-existence is uneasy, because invoking the specter of the law undermines the commitment contained in a promise from the perspective of both promisor and promisee. The content of that commitment is possible only within a close personal relationship. It entails a combining of interests that were previously separately held by promisor and promisee. In a private promise, the promisor undertakes to give the promisee's relevant interests weight equal to or greater than her own. The specter of legal liability creates a reason for performance stemming from the separateness rather than the unity of interests between promisor and promisee. A sincere intent on the part of the promisor to perform for reasons unrelated to legal obligation does not dissipate this tension any more than a sincere intent on the part of the more powerful party in a dispute to resolve that dispute fairly would render her unilateral decision just.Once we have disentangled private and legal promise, we can begin to adjust the boundaries and defaults of contract law accordingly. Because private promises are private, contract law should make it relatively costly for parties to bring the law to bear on such commitments; indeed, it already does. When public policy dictates affording a legal remedy for the breach of private promise, we can mitigate the conflict between private and legal promise by minimizing their overlap. This can be (and, in part, already is) done by limiting the remedies for breach to ones which the private promise did not contemplate. In fact, the remedy should deviate from both the obligations imposed by private promissory norms and the remedy usually awarded in commercial cases. In the context of personal relationships, reliance damages should be the preferred remedy. Reliance damages redress the injury inflicted by breach of the promise, in which the state may have a legitimate interest, but do not have the effect of either coercing performance or rendering the promisee indifferent to performance.In other contexts, the distinction between private and legal promise calls for an expansion of the domain of contract. For example, promises made in the context of radical inequality in power, as in most employment circumstances, are often located outside the law. A promisor with vastly superior bargaining power need not promise in the contractual form in order to induce the desired conduct by the promisee; the promisor has no incentive to submit the unequal relationship to legal authority. Downward promises between hierarchically situated persons are not easily enforced by the state. Thus, performance of those promises usually remains at the discretion of the promisor. Such promises are false private promises. To the extent we see the depersonalization of the employment relationship as an important achievement of the liberal market economy, this account clarifies one task of contract law: the displacement of private promise in the realm of employment. Just as parties should have to go out of their way to make a private promise legally binding, legal defaults should make it relatively onerous for employers to avoid legal consequence when they make promises to their employees." @default.
- W1568787489 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W1568787489 creator A5065682125 @default.
- W1568787489 date "2007-09-11" @default.
- W1568787489 modified "2023-09-28" @default.
- W1568787489 title "Separating Contract and Promise" @default.
- W1568787489 hasPublicationYear "2007" @default.
- W1568787489 type Work @default.
- W1568787489 sameAs 1568787489 @default.
- W1568787489 citedByCount "0" @default.
- W1568787489 crossrefType "posted-content" @default.
- W1568787489 hasAuthorship W1568787489A5065682125 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConcept C144024400 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConcept C144133560 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConcept C17744445 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConcept C190253527 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConcept C199539241 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConcept C2777381055 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConcept C2777834853 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConcept C2778877846 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConceptScore W1568787489C144024400 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConceptScore W1568787489C144133560 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConceptScore W1568787489C17744445 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConceptScore W1568787489C190253527 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConceptScore W1568787489C199539241 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConceptScore W1568787489C2777381055 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConceptScore W1568787489C2777834853 @default.
- W1568787489 hasConceptScore W1568787489C2778877846 @default.
- W1568787489 hasLocation W15687874891 @default.
- W1568787489 hasOpenAccess W1568787489 @default.
- W1568787489 hasPrimaryLocation W15687874891 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W1535606159 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W1577768363 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W1599481068 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W1988217278 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W209116770 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W2097343667 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W2102146356 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W2192719686 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W2261911556 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W2506713245 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W2580479451 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W2596481114 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W3084257013 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W3122046395 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W3124621890 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W3131505792 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W3135542363 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W3135687096 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W2096419206 @default.
- W1568787489 hasRelatedWork W3124368701 @default.
- W1568787489 isParatext "false" @default.
- W1568787489 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W1568787489 magId "1568787489" @default.
- W1568787489 workType "article" @default.