Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W1972717207> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 82 of
82
with 100 items per page.
- W1972717207 endingPage "243" @default.
- W1972717207 startingPage "225" @default.
- W1972717207 abstract "In Idea, a thousand nameless Joys: Secondary Qualities in Arnauld, Locke, and Haywood's Lasselia Helen Thompson Northwestern University Cartesian dualism is articulated as a particular kind of conundrum in Descartes' Sixth Meditation (1640), where he advances the proof that I have a body. Here, the incompatibility of Descartes's I and his body assumes its most impacted, most aggravated, and, paradoxically, its most resolvable and irresolvable form when Descartes narrates the event of perception: Nature . . . teaches me . . . that I am not merely present in my body as a sailor is present in a ship, but that I am very closely joined and, as it were, intermingled with it, so that I and the body form a unit. If this were not so, I, who am nothing but a thinking thing, would not feel pain when the body was hurt, but would perceive the damage purely by the intellect, just as a sailor perceives by sight if anything in his ship is broken. Similarly, when the body needed food or drink, I should have an explicit understanding of the fact, instead of having confused sensations of hunger and thirst. For these sensations of hunger, thirst, pain and so on are nothing but confused modes of thinking which arise from the union and, as it were, intermingling of the mind with the body.1 In this passage, Descartes maintains his commitment to the difference between extended (divisible, hence imperfect) body and unextended (indivisible, hence divinized) mind. But at the same time, he concedes the confused sensations, the confused modes of thinking, the union, and the intermingling which transpire when, for example, he feels hunger. Rather than incarnating a mind-body split that would, so to speak, cut through Descartes himself, he is compelled by sensations like thirst, pain, or desire to reject the hypostatized figure of rationality modeled by the sailor in his ship. Yet as the Sixth Meditation proceeds, Descartes revises his account of the intermingling of mind and body which accompanies either sensations like hunger or sensory [End Page 225] perceptions about things located outside us. This is so not simply because a person mistakes things like the real size of the star that she perceives as the flame of a small light,2 but also because the insight proven, for Descartes, by the star—that its truth can be adjudicated only by the intellect—applies equally to a person's perception of her own body. For Descartes, movement that stimulates the body ultimately bears no likeness3 to feelings which result inside the brain, a discrepancy he vividly illustrates in Principles of Philosophy (1644): A sword strikes our body and cuts it; but the ensuing pain is completely different from the local motion of the sword or the body that is cut—as different as colour or sound or smell or taste.4 Even in this maximally entangled scene of intermingling, the mind might indeed behave like a sailor in a ship when it judges the truth of external objects; Descartes divorces ensuing ideas from sensory stimulation which cuts into the matter of the body itself. A close reader of Descartes, John Locke makes the anti-Cartesian argument that ideas enter the mind only through the medium of the body.5 (However immaterial it may be, Locke's mind harbors no innate ideas of divinity.) Yet Locke's An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690) recurs to the Cartesian example of the sword when Locke likewise invokes the swath of aesthetic sensations remote from the insensible particles of matter that move a person to perceive color or sound or smell or taste: It being no more impossible, to conceive, that God should annex such Ideas to such Motions, with which they have no similitude; then that he should annex the Idea of Pain to the motion of a piece of Steel dividing our Flesh, with which that Idea hath no resemblance.6 In the following essay, I pursue the..." @default.
- W1972717207 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W1972717207 creator A5084555868 @default.
- W1972717207 date "2007-01-01" @default.
- W1972717207 modified "2023-10-17" @default.
- W1972717207 title "In Idea, a thousand nameless Joys: Secondary Qualities in Arnauld, Locke, and Haywood's Lasselia" @default.
- W1972717207 cites W1530415884 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W1591422284 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W166834640 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W1815189098 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W1964252948 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W1972661466 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W2000008457 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W2002265975 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W2003396434 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W2012450445 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W2018455061 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W2062159679 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W2065546275 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W2070038867 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W2127699458 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W287151347 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W3188126393 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W325659957 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W641551747 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W649474106 @default.
- W1972717207 cites W83471228 @default.
- W1972717207 doi "https://doi.org/10.1353/ecy.2008.0006" @default.
- W1972717207 hasPublicationYear "2007" @default.
- W1972717207 type Work @default.
- W1972717207 sameAs 1972717207 @default.
- W1972717207 citedByCount "5" @default.
- W1972717207 countsByYear W19727172072013 @default.
- W1972717207 countsByYear W19727172072014 @default.
- W1972717207 countsByYear W19727172072017 @default.
- W1972717207 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W1972717207 hasAuthorship W1972717207A5084555868 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C11171543 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C119599485 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C127413603 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C136815107 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C15744967 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C20497413 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C2776202085 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C2780146897 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C2780822299 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConcept C54531595 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C111472728 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C11171543 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C119599485 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C127413603 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C136815107 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C138885662 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C15744967 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C20497413 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C2776202085 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C2780146897 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C2780822299 @default.
- W1972717207 hasConceptScore W1972717207C54531595 @default.
- W1972717207 hasIssue "3" @default.
- W1972717207 hasLocation W19727172071 @default.
- W1972717207 hasOpenAccess W1972717207 @default.
- W1972717207 hasPrimaryLocation W19727172071 @default.
- W1972717207 hasRelatedWork W1013932942 @default.
- W1972717207 hasRelatedWork W1963578324 @default.
- W1972717207 hasRelatedWork W1972717207 @default.
- W1972717207 hasRelatedWork W2073613117 @default.
- W1972717207 hasRelatedWork W2178170871 @default.
- W1972717207 hasRelatedWork W2360044791 @default.
- W1972717207 hasRelatedWork W2604847138 @default.
- W1972717207 hasRelatedWork W2775529474 @default.
- W1972717207 hasRelatedWork W2887723078 @default.
- W1972717207 hasRelatedWork W3101616969 @default.
- W1972717207 hasVolume "48" @default.
- W1972717207 isParatext "false" @default.
- W1972717207 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W1972717207 magId "1972717207" @default.
- W1972717207 workType "article" @default.