Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W1999398028> ?p ?o ?g. }
- W1999398028 endingPage "40" @default.
- W1999398028 startingPage "16" @default.
- W1999398028 abstract "Aristotle’s Phantasia in the Rhetoric:Lexis, Appearance, and the Epideictic Function of Discourse Ned O’Gorman Introduction The well-known opening line of Aristotle's Rhetoric, where he defines rhetoric as a counterpart (antistrophos) to dialectic, has spurred many conversations on Aristotelian rhetoric and motivated the widespread interpretation of Aristotle's theory of civic discourse as heavily rationalistic. This study starts from a statement in the Rhetoric less discussed, yet still important, that suggests that a visual aspect inheres in Aristotle's theory of rhetoric. Near the beginning of book 3, which deals with lexis (style, sometimes subsuming delivery1 ), Aristotle conjoins lexis and phantasia with the copula is (eimi): The subject of expression [lexeôs], however, has some small necessary place in all teaching; for to speak in one way rather than another does make some difference in regard to clarity, though not a great difference; but all these things are forms of outward show [phantasia] and intended to affect the audience (1404a).2 Whereas scholars exploring the relationship between rhetoric and dialectic have compared and contrasted the Rhetoric and the Topics, I explore rhetoric's relationship with phantasia by reading the Rhetoric alongside De Anima. De Anima is Aristotle's seminal account of the senses and their relationship to psychê (often translated soul). It addresses topics intimately connected to rhetoric: perception, cognition, deliberation, visualization, imagination, and the image. Phantasia is integral to each of these psychic processes and to Aristotle's understanding of the function of appearance in human experience. Hence, itis a lens suitable for exploring the relationship between Aristotle's conception of civic discourse and his notions of sight and appearances as they relate to perception, interpretation, deliberation, and judgment. I find in Aristotle's phantasia a tie between his art of rhetoric and his psychology and phenomenology (anachronistic though these terms are). Aristotle's psychological works, as Richard McKeon points out, are foundational to Aristotle's philosophy, and thus to his Rhetoric. [End Page 16] Psychological inquiries occupy an extremely important position in the philosophy of Aristotle, for the conception of the psychê lays the foundation for the continuity of functions in nature (1947, 142). De Anima, especially, articulates the psychological and phenomenological conceptions often tacitly at work in the Rhetoric. The importance of phantasia for the trajectory of ancient rhetorical and aesthetic theory is seen in the parallels between the visual arts, rhetoric, and poetics in Greek and Roman thought.3 As David Freedberg states (perhaps, slightly overstates), parallels between painting and poetry are to be found everywhere in classical literature (1989, 50). With respect to such visual-verbal parallels in Aristotle, D. Thomas Benediktson's reading of Aristotle's psychological, poetic, and rhetorical works concludes that phantasia ties together the visual and the literary. [Aristotle's passages on phantasia] do help to see why Aristotle took for granted the similarity, almost the identity, of literature and the visual arts. Both types of art are imagistic; they present to the viewer either an image, as in visual art, or as in literature, a set of moving images that the soul then uses as raw data (phantasia) to enable thought to occur (2000, 170). Phantasia developed a legacy in Hellenistic aesthetics, where it came to designate suprarealism in painting, moving art beyond imitation (Fowler 1989, 180–81). In later Greco-Roman works, phantasia was used to designate vivid imagery in written and oral discourse, imagery that could create sights and scenes in the minds of audience members. As Quintilian noted in his discussion of forensic rhetoric, in Latin phantasiai were termed visiones. Here, phantasiabecame a mode of displacing narrative in rhetorical discourse: There are certain experiences which the Greeks call phantasiai, and the Romans visions [visiones], whereby things absent are presented to our imagination with such extreme vividness that they seem actually to be before our very eyes. . . . From such impressions arises that enargeia which Cicero calls illumination [illustration] and actuality [evidential], which makes us seem not so much to narrate [dicere] as to exhibit [ostendere] the actual scene. (Institutio Oratoria 4.2.29, 32) Quintilian's invocations of phantasia and enargeia can be traced to Aristotle's discussion of rhetorical style in book..." @default.
- W1999398028 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W1999398028 creator A5048695388 @default.
- W1999398028 date "2005-01-01" @default.
- W1999398028 modified "2023-10-18" @default.
- W1999398028 title "Aristotle's Phantasia in the Rhetoric : Lexis, Appearance, and the Epideictic Function of Discourse" @default.
- W1999398028 cites W1487238404 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W1531845849 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W1581645817 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W1602719501 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W1965739466 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W1973585071 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W1980112458 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W1993522382 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W1994686529 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W1995173209 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2014509837 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2015462985 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2015732762 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2031562375 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2034064481 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2034645465 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2053367043 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2057301790 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2067251193 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2070992571 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2073515212 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2079227492 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2082626220 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2088022120 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2091291303 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2155271177 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2313428595 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2320984177 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2330418595 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2331611289 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2395005638 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2489648762 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2502061015 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2508188243 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2587129802 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2612675639 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W298232870 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W568129244 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W569303365 @default.
- W1999398028 cites W2474408561 @default.
- W1999398028 doi "https://doi.org/10.1353/par.2005.0009" @default.
- W1999398028 hasPublicationYear "2005" @default.
- W1999398028 type Work @default.
- W1999398028 sameAs 1999398028 @default.
- W1999398028 citedByCount "36" @default.
- W1999398028 countsByYear W19993980282013 @default.
- W1999398028 countsByYear W19993980282015 @default.
- W1999398028 countsByYear W19993980282016 @default.
- W1999398028 countsByYear W19993980282017 @default.
- W1999398028 countsByYear W19993980282018 @default.
- W1999398028 countsByYear W19993980282019 @default.
- W1999398028 countsByYear W19993980282020 @default.
- W1999398028 countsByYear W19993980282021 @default.
- W1999398028 countsByYear W19993980282022 @default.
- W1999398028 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W1999398028 hasAuthorship W1999398028A5048695388 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C107038049 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C124952713 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C13184196 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C1370556 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C142362112 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C144024400 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C164913051 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C41895202 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C516687495 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C527412718 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C556248259 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConcept C63075964 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C107038049 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C111472728 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C124952713 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C13184196 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C1370556 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C138885662 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C142362112 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C144024400 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C164913051 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C41895202 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C516687495 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C527412718 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C556248259 @default.
- W1999398028 hasConceptScore W1999398028C63075964 @default.
- W1999398028 hasIssue "1" @default.
- W1999398028 hasLocation W19993980281 @default.
- W1999398028 hasOpenAccess W1999398028 @default.
- W1999398028 hasPrimaryLocation W19993980281 @default.
- W1999398028 hasRelatedWork W1499017723 @default.
- W1999398028 hasRelatedWork W1994686529 @default.
- W1999398028 hasRelatedWork W2007594705 @default.
- W1999398028 hasRelatedWork W2036610618 @default.