Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2000846232> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 74 of
74
with 100 items per page.
- W2000846232 endingPage "251" @default.
- W2000846232 startingPage "227" @default.
- W2000846232 abstract "Kant, Mendelssohn, Lambert, and the Subjectivity of Time LORNE FALKENSTEIN KANTFREQUENTLYCLAIMSthat space and time are subjective conditions of our sensitivity.' This is often--and quite naturally--taken to mean that they are imposed by the mind on the objects of knowledge, as if nothing apart from our mental representations exhibited spatio-temporal properties; rather our minds are so constituted that we inject spatio-temporal form into our mental representations.' I believe that this view is mistaken. In what follows I will show that though Kant did indeed sustain an imposition thesis in his Inaugural Dissertation of 177o (hereafter cited as ID), he carefully rejected it in his later work. One of the motivating factors behind this change may have been an objecReferences to space and time as subjective conditions or as grounded on the constitution (Beschaffenheit) of the subject are widespread in Kant's works. A26 = B42 and A3~-33 = B49 can perhaps be taken as the canonical instances, as it is here that the claim is first stated under the title of an established conclusion (from the metaphysical and transcendental expositions of the Transcendental Aesthetic). References to Kant's Critique ofPure Reason are to the pagination of the first and second original editions (Leipzig: Johann Friedrich Hartknoch, 1781 and 1787), cited as 'A' and 'B' respectively. References to his other works are to the pagination of the Prussian Academy edidon of Kant's collected writings (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1968), cited as 'Ak' with volume and page in arabic numerals. Translations from Kant's German are my own. Those from his Latin follow Kerferd in G. B. Kerferd and D. E. Walford, Kant: Selected Pre-Critical Writings (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1968). ' Witness Strawson's references to a physiological model of perception underlying (what he takes to be) Kant's posidon (P. F. Strawson, The Bound, of Sense [London: Methuen, 1966], 15-16, 39-40. The same account of Kant's thought is offered by H. A. Prichard, Kant's Theory of Knowledge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 19o9), 3o-32. The colored spectacles analogy, frequently used to explicate Kant's position (see H. J. Paton, Kant's Metaphysic of Experience [London: Allen and Unwin, 1936], 1: x66; A. C. Ewing, A Short Commentary on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd ed. [London: Methuen, 195o], 3o; Stephan Koerner, Kant [Harmondsworth, England: Penguin, 1955], 37) is based on the same picture. Explicit statements that for Kant space and time are imposed by the mind on sensation can be found in Jonathan Bennett, Kant's Dialectic (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974), 54-56, and Paul Guyer, Kant and the Claims of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 361. [~'71 228 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 29:2 APRIL 1991 tion to ID which Kant received from a number of his colleagues in 177o and 1771--an objection which points out a serious inconsistency in the theory of mental imposition. I will describe this objection in Part 1 below,3 and in Part 2 I will argue that it constitutes a decisive refutation of the imposition thesis and of ID's consequent claims about the ideality of knowledge based on sensory experience. The thesis of Part 2 is a philosophical one--that the imposition thesis is exploded by the objection Kant's colleagues presented, and that if he continued to sustain it, then he did so either by failing to appreciate the force of the objection or by overestimating the adequacy of his response. In Part 3 I will complement this philosophical point with a historical one: that in his later work Kant abandoned the imposition thesis and instead relied upon a much more conservative account of what it means for space and time to be subjective . Part 4 will show that this revised position is adequate to escape the 177o objection. If I am right, then, whatever Kant may have meant by the subjectivity of space and time, he did not mean that they can apply only to the subject's mental representations. One consequence of this conclusion will be the by now familiar thesis that Kant's transcendental idealism cannot be a form of phenomenalism . But a further, more important consequence..." @default.
- W2000846232 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W2000846232 creator A5081768873 @default.
- W2000846232 date "1991-01-01" @default.
- W2000846232 modified "2023-10-17" @default.
- W2000846232 title "Kant, Mendelssohn, Lambert, and the Subjectivity of Time" @default.
- W2000846232 cites W1535435425 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W1557386097 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W1922572395 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W1987808590 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W1991054048 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W1993523683 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W2000040022 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W2016338498 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W2081043387 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W21109096 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W2396917733 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W2493890242 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W381831150 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W419576420 @default.
- W2000846232 cites W789176329 @default.
- W2000846232 doi "https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.1991.0046" @default.
- W2000846232 hasPublicationYear "1991" @default.
- W2000846232 type Work @default.
- W2000846232 sameAs 2000846232 @default.
- W2000846232 citedByCount "2" @default.
- W2000846232 countsByYear W20008462322017 @default.
- W2000846232 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2000846232 hasAuthorship W2000846232A5081768873 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C124952713 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C136815107 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C142362112 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C161191863 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C182744844 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C188370112 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C196595271 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C202889954 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C2777855551 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConcept C41008148 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C111472728 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C124952713 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C136815107 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C138885662 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C142362112 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C161191863 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C182744844 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C188370112 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C196595271 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C202889954 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C2777855551 @default.
- W2000846232 hasConceptScore W2000846232C41008148 @default.
- W2000846232 hasIssue "2" @default.
- W2000846232 hasLocation W20008462321 @default.
- W2000846232 hasOpenAccess W2000846232 @default.
- W2000846232 hasPrimaryLocation W20008462321 @default.
- W2000846232 hasRelatedWork W1825709112 @default.
- W2000846232 hasRelatedWork W2128747134 @default.
- W2000846232 hasRelatedWork W2556008354 @default.
- W2000846232 hasRelatedWork W2565127641 @default.
- W2000846232 hasRelatedWork W263676812 @default.
- W2000846232 hasRelatedWork W2900800520 @default.
- W2000846232 hasRelatedWork W2940062896 @default.
- W2000846232 hasRelatedWork W2963045966 @default.
- W2000846232 hasRelatedWork W2999138942 @default.
- W2000846232 hasRelatedWork W4285222728 @default.
- W2000846232 hasVolume "29" @default.
- W2000846232 isParatext "false" @default.
- W2000846232 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W2000846232 magId "2000846232" @default.
- W2000846232 workType "article" @default.