Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2004336532> ?p ?o ?g. }
- W2004336532 endingPage "590" @default.
- W2004336532 startingPage "584" @default.
- W2004336532 abstract "Science & Society15 June 2012Open Access Engineering and ethical perspectives in synthetic biology Rigorous, robust and predictable designs, public engagement and a modern ethical framework are vital to the continued success of synthetic biology. James Anderson James Anderson Department of Engineering Science, University of Oxford, UK Search for more papers by this author Natalja Strelkowa Natalja Strelkowa Department of Bioengineering, Imperial College London, UK Search for more papers by this author Guy-Bart Stan Guy-Bart Stan Department of Bioengineering, Imperial College London, UK Search for more papers by this author Thomas Douglas Thomas Douglas Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, University of Oxford, UK Search for more papers by this author Julian Savulescu Julian Savulescu Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, University of Oxford, UK Search for more papers by this author Mauricio Barahona Mauricio Barahona Department of Mathematics, Imperial College London, UK Search for more papers by this author Antonis Papachristodoulou Antonis Papachristodoulou Department of Engineering Science and the Oxford Centre for Integrative Systems Biology, University of Oxford, UK Search for more papers by this author James Anderson James Anderson Department of Engineering Science, University of Oxford, UK Search for more papers by this author Natalja Strelkowa Natalja Strelkowa Department of Bioengineering, Imperial College London, UK Search for more papers by this author Guy-Bart Stan Guy-Bart Stan Department of Bioengineering, Imperial College London, UK Search for more papers by this author Thomas Douglas Thomas Douglas Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, University of Oxford, UK Search for more papers by this author Julian Savulescu Julian Savulescu Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, University of Oxford, UK Search for more papers by this author Mauricio Barahona Mauricio Barahona Department of Mathematics, Imperial College London, UK Search for more papers by this author Antonis Papachristodoulou Antonis Papachristodoulou Department of Engineering Science and the Oxford Centre for Integrative Systems Biology, University of Oxford, UK Search for more papers by this author Author Information James Anderson1, Natalja Strelkowa2, Guy-Bart Stan2, Thomas Douglas3, Julian Savulescu3, Mauricio Barahona4 and Antonis Papachristodoulou5 1Department of Engineering Science, University of Oxford, UK 2Department of Bioengineering, Imperial College London, UK 3Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, University of Oxford, UK 4Department of Mathematics, Imperial College London, UK 5Department of Engineering Science and the Oxford Centre for Integrative Systems Biology, University of Oxford, UK EMBO Reports (2012)13:584-590https://doi.org/10.1038/embor.2012.81 PDFDownload PDF of article text and main figures. ToolsAdd to favoritesDownload CitationsTrack CitationsPermissions ShareFacebookTwitterLinked InMendeleyWechatReddit Figures & Info Synthetic biology has emerged as an exciting and promising new research field, garnering significant attention from both the scientific community and the general public. This interest results from a variety of striking features: synthetic biology is a truly interdisciplinary field that engages biologists, mathematicians, physicists and engineers; its research focus is applied; and it has enormous potential to harness the power of biology to provide scientific and engineering solutions to a wide range of problems and challenges that plague humanity. However, the power of synthetic biology to engineer organisms with custom-made functionality requires that researchers and society use this power safely and responsibly, in particular when it comes to releasing organisms into the environment. This creates new challenges for both the design of such organisms and the regulatory process governing their creation and use. …the power of synthetic biology to engineer organisms with custom-made functionality requires that researchers and society use this power safely and responsibly… As synthetic biology is being defined and developed by researchers spanning several fields, it is hardly surprising that a unified definition of synthetic biology is lacking. For the purposes of this paper, we define synthetic biology as ‘the endeavour to design new, or modify existing, organisms to produce biological systems with new or enhanced functionality according to quantifiable design criteria’, because it explicitly requires that the synthetic system can be evaluated against a quantifiable design objective as is done in traditional engineering. The origins of synthetic biology go back to 1979, when the Nobel Prize-winning chemist Har Gobind Khorana synthesized a 207 base-pair DNA sequence [1]. Since that breakthrough, the size and complexity of synthetic DNA molecules has rapidly increased, culminating in 2010 with the successful synthesis of the 1.08 Mbp Mycoplasma mycoides genome, which is capable of self-replication [2]. This breakthrough prompted US President Barack Obama to commission a report on the safety implications of synthetic biology. In December 2010, the Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues (PCSBI) reported to the White House and “found no reason to endorse further federal regulations or a moratorium to work in this field at this time” [3]. The report recommended that scientists should regulate themselves and pointed out the need for “scientific, religious and civic engagement with the public”. Such recommendations, especially in regard to public engagement, had already been made by the main UK funding bodies: the Engineering and Physical Sciences Research Council (EPSRC), the Biotechnology and Biological Sciences Research Council (BBSRC), the Economic and Social Research Council (ESRC) and the Arts and Humanities Research Council (AHRC). The rationale for such studies and reports is the enormous potential of synthetic biology to develop new biological organisms capable of carrying out functions useful to industry and society, such as waste degradation, water toxicity detection, biofuel production, drug development and so on. Many of the applications of synthetic biology ultimately involve the release of synthetic organisms into the environment. In addition to raising social and ethical issues, this creates major scientific and engineering challenges, in particular the need to design robust and predictable synthetic organisms. Thus, until we are capable of constructing synthetic organisms that meet strictly defined design criteria—in which future behaviour is predictable in the presence of intrinsic and extrinsic noise, uncertainty and evolutionary action—scientists and society should exercise caution before synthetic organisms are allowed to leave the confines of the laboratory. Robustness requirements, such as these, need to be incorporated into the synthetic biology research cycle as is common practice in other engineering disciplines (Fig 1). Figure 1.Interaction between the three key subject areas in synthetic biology. Download figure Download PowerPoint Technological systems of staggering complexity, such as digital computers, power grids and the Internet, have become such an integral part of our lives that we take them for granted. Their success owes, in large measure, to the modular design strategy that engineers use to deal with escalating levels of complexity and conflicting requirements. A large system is typically designed by using a ‘top-down’ approach: the problem is divided into a hierarchical set of smaller sub-problems for which it is easier to design and implement smaller subsystems using existing and well-characterized modules that solve these sub-problems. The task is complete when the overall design has been successfully tested and verified, to guarantee that the system performs according to the specifications to which it was designed. If the design is not modular and hierarchical, verification rapidly becomes intractable. Contrary to typical engineering designs, biology exploits unavoidable variability to ensure robustness and adaptation to changing environments Unfortunately, it is not always clear what constitutes a module in biological systems, nor how modules can be interconnected. One way to define a modular structure in natural genetic circuits is through ‘network motifs’, interaction patterns that occur frequently in complex networks and that could be associated with particular functionalities. Such motifs can range in scale from localized bimolecular interactions to complete pathways, such as linear cascades or coherent and incoherent feed-forward loops. Although various algorithms have been developed to identify such motifs in protein–protein and genetic networks in Escherichia coli and Saccharomyces cerevisiae [4], the relationship between network motifs and the dynamic functionality of the whole network is still unclear. This conceptual gap needs to be resolved if we are to use natural modules systematically to redesign predictable and robust synthetic organisms. It is therefore not surprising that the first synthetic systems used simpler configurations, rather than adaptations of more complex biological networks, to achieve a particular functionality. Instead, those constructions were based on classical engineering design principles (Table 1). Table 1. Engineering, natural and synthetic solutions for designing complex systems Design challenge Engineering solution Natural organism Synthetic biology solution Scalability Modularity MotifsModularity? ModularityWell-characterized modules Retroactivity/cross-talk Insulation and feedback Feedback Orthogonal design Robustness Feedback Feedback Feedback Complexity Hierarchical design ? Hierarchical design Evolution/mutation ? Efficiency/robustness trade-off ? Part of the success of synthetic biology to date has depended on a measure of modularity, through the creation of a standard library of parts, that enables a ‘plug-and-play’ framework for biological circuits. The idea is to develop a library of standardized genetic modules with specific functionality that can be combined to achieve a certain function, analogous to binary transistor logic libraries used by electrical engineers. The Massachusetts Institute of Technology (MIT) Registry of Standard Biological Parts is, at the time of writing, the most popular example (http://partsregistry.org/). Although the ‘second wave of synthetic biology’ [5] now focuses on the interconnections of such modules, the issue of modularity is still open to debate [6]. The question is whether modularity is a natural property, or whether it is an abstraction imposed by engineers to simplify the design of complex systems. One school of thought asserts that abstraction should be enforced in synthetic designs to achieve scalability, predictability and robustness. The opposing view contends that dictating that all synthetic biology designs must be modular, can lead to unworkable constructs and significantly restricts the design options. At the other end of the spectrum, engineers must make sure that their designs are ‘robust’ to noise and perturbations, or, put another way, can operate in the presence of uncertainty. Such robustness is achieved, often at great cost, typically through the use of feedback loops [7]. However, making a system robust to a particular set of perturbations can make it fragile to other perturbations, which results in ‘robust yet fragile’ behaviour [8]. If the designer is aware of this constraint, he or she can ensure that overall fragilities are rare. A commercial airliner for instance has been designed to be robust to perturbations such as cargo load variation, atmospheric changes or ageing material. Each of these perturbations occur over different but known spatial and temporal timescales. However, unanticipated microscopic damage to a few core processors on board could have catastrophic consequences. In the context of synthetic biology, the balance between robustness and fragility is extremely important. Consider as an example the case of a synthetic biosensor to detect land mines [9]. Researchers would have to create designs and describe various biochemical reactions and the organism's interactions with the desired target. However, only a finite number of probable interactions can realistically be modelled. Furthermore, each interaction can be modelled only with respect to a few parameters, such as temperature, pH levels, kinetic constants, evolutionary fitness and so on. Assuming the constructed organism satisfies all the design criteria and is robust to the uncertainty just described, is it reasonable to release it into the field? Clearly, the job of detecting land mines is a worthy cause; however, there are probably many other factors that the biosensor encounters that have not been modelled or accounted for, or for which the parameters considered during the modelling phase are not valid. Simple organisms use feedback to achieve such robustness—the classic example is chemotaxis in E. coli [10]. Robustness applied to synthetic biology should ensure that the dynamic behaviour of the engineered organism is not sensitive to ‘small’ expected fluctuations in the environment in which it operates. However, one of the fundamental challenges for synthetic biology is to account for the uncertain environment that the synthetic organism might eventually inhabit. This uncertainty is caused by a variety of factors—high levels of noise, adaptation and evolution at the organism and population levels, and uncharacterized cross-talk between modules—and is fundamentally different from that typically accounted for in engineering. A systems engineering approach to synthetic biology advocates a separation of the design into two distinct layers: the design of individual components or modules to create the desired functionality, and the design of their interconnection structure and communication mechanisms. Two key issues under debate are whether natural systems can be interpreted as hierarchically organized modules, and conversely, to what extent synthetic biologists can learn from the interconnection architecture of natural systems (Table 1). These two questions lead naturally to the overlap between synthetic and systems biology. The latter studies the organizational structure of natural systems to derive simplified models, by using assumptions such as modularity and hierarchical layering. Indeed, there are similarities between natural and man-made complex systems in terms of their organizational structure, as illustrated in [11] by using a Lego brick analogy. However, despite these apparent organizational similarities, some of the defining properties of biological systems, such as their natural ability to evolve, raise fundamental theoretical challenges. A main obstacle to designing predictable and robust biological circuits, is the requirement for exact input–output properties of modules both in isolation and when interconnected. Many of the synthetic parts in the MIT registry are poorly characterized in regard to their dynamic behaviour in isolation and under varying biological environments. This is in part caused by a lack of knowledge about the environmental variables that can affect biological behaviour. In a classical engineering set-up, a sufficient description for a module would involve a predictable input–output behaviour, characterized by parameters that can be varied to suit key properties—such as operating temperature, pressure, energy source and so on—that define the state of the environment in which the module is to operate. In biological design, many of the environmental properties that determine the behaviour of a module have not been identified, or have been identified but not modelled owing to their complexity. Even if we assume that a module is fully characterized in isolation, there are further challenges related directly to our ability to predict the behaviour of an ensemble of interconnected modules. One such obstacle is ‘retroactivity’—feedback from downstream events and elements that typically propagates information in a direction opposite to that which is normally anticipated [12]. Such effects are relevant because any useful synthetic organism is probably formed from multiple interconnected modules. From an engineering perspective, each module is designed so that retroactivity is attenuated around the desired operating point of the system. An example of retroactivity is a cascade of hydraulic tanks: when water flows from an upstream tank to a downstream tank, the water pressure in the upstream tank changes. The result is a flow of information in both directions although the input to output behaviour acts only downstream. Retroactivity in cellular biology appears when an upstream promoter experiences feedback from the activation of downstream promoters, as observed experimentally in the nitrogen assimilation control system of E. coli [13]. It has been shown, however, that long phosphorylation and dephosphorylation cascades can significantly attenuate retroactivity [14]. Thus, one possible solution could be to incorporate these cascades into synthetic constructs to increase the level of modularity of the designed system. Another difficulty for designing predictable behaviour in interconnected modules is the fact that different connected modules might have varying sensitivity to the intra- and intercellular environment. Consider, for example, a synthetic organism that is designed for waste degradation [15] and assume that such an organism comprises several modules. In addition to the differing sensitivity of the connected modules to intra and intercellular environments under laboratory conditions, the variable and uncertain environment in which they are to be released will push the operation of the engineered organism to its robustness limit. With respect to waste degradation, this potential lack of robustness is a severe problem, as a population of synthetic organisms would need to be sustained to be effective. Unique to this example is the fact that once the synthetic organism—which for the sake of argument we shall say is ‘robust’—has achieved its goal, it might not be desirable to continue the synthetic population. An overly robust organism might even become problematic unless we can control where the ‘fragility’ occurs and use this as a form of population control. By maintaining this line of thought it might be possible to specifically engineer fragility in such a manner that the synthetic organisms are ‘evolutionary losers’. When the synthetic organisms are released into the open environment they will be outcompeted by their natural counterpart and eventually die off. Another solution to address intra- and intercellular sensitivity is to design ‘orthogonal’ modules that do not interfere with each other. Recent work [16] created a synthetic pathway in E. coli on the basis of the idea of transcription and translation mechanisms that are orthogonal to those naturally present in the bacterial host cell. One of the most challenging aspects of synthetic biology is the engineering of evolution A theoretical approach for designing a controllable synthetic circuit has been proposed [17,18] and could be applied in similar situations. The principal idea is to incorporate an outer feedback loop around the synthetic construct, such that the organism cannot be sustained without an external control signal: a given nutrient or a light source. This type of approach guarantees that the engineered organism cannot survive unaided in the environment and will eventually die off when the control signal is no longer applied (Fig 2). However, the predictability of evolution and adaptation of synthetic organisms is limited. Indeed, population-level dynamical adaptation, noise during gene expression and continuing reproduction need to be taken into account both at the design stage and as part of the experimental verification. Figure 2.Conceptual idea of incorporating a feedback signal to sustain a synthetic population. Download figure Download PowerPoint Biological systems are subject to high levels of both extrinsic noise and intrinsic stochasticity, owing to low copy numbers of DNA and mRNA [19]. Typically, feedback loops are used to attenuate the effects of noise. However, the level of noise in natural organisms far exceeds that of man-made systems. Furthermore, cells are able to use noise as a signalling mechanism. Contrary to typical engineering designs, biology exploits unavoidable variability to ensure robustness and adaptation to changing environments. Therefore, a synthetic design principle can either be to construct modules that are robust to noise or to explicitly use the stochastic nature of the cellular environment in the design process. In the former case, recent work [20] has addressed the fundamental limits of suppressing molecular fluctuation as a function of the signalling rate. Synthetic circuits might therefore require a hybrid solution that incorporates both design principles. One of the most challenging aspects of synthetic biology is the engineering of evolution. The possibility that a designed biological component might in future generations cease to exist or, worse yet, might mutate into something different raises important ethical and practical questions. Evolution and mutation do not fit into any of the existing theoretical frameworks for robustness or modelling, although work in this direction has already begun both experimentally [21] and theoretically [22]. In the former case, randomized non-essential sequences were inserted into DNA sequences that code for a simple feed-forward loop. The resulting synthetic constructs still meet the design criteria, although the non-essential sequences were shown to have an effect on dynamic functionality. In the latter work, the authors developed a dynamic model that accounts for the adaptive behaviour seen in E. coli that fits with general evolutionary principles. From a conceptual point of view it might be helpful to think of evolution, mutation and adaptation as a type of discrete uncertainty, in a mathematical sense, that affects the long-term dynamics of a synthetic organism. In comparison, intrinsic and extrinsic noise could be viewed as short-term continuous effects. In almost all natural cells, the genetic code contains redundant or at least non-coding sequences termed ‘junk DNA’. In many cases, junk DNA contains transposons that cause mutations and genes whose function is unknown—possible relics from previous evolutionary steps. In keeping with the ‘minimal genome’ hypothesis, previous work developed an E. coli genome with much of this junk DNA removed [23]. It showed that the synthesized bacteria had exactly the same growth rate properties as the wild type. In theory, minimal genome organisms should also reduce the risk of mutation and evolution and provide a solid basis for enforcing modularity and minimal designs in synthetic biology. It is vital that future design frameworks consider evolution, to ensure that synthetic organisms behave as predicted over longer timescales, and are thus compliant from a biosafety standpoint. In terms of moving synthetic biology from the lab to real world applications it is perhaps this challenge that most needs a solution. From an industrial perspective, efficiency usually means yield maximization or minimal resource utilization. From a biological perspective, this utilitarian perspective—in an economical and mathematical sense—does not share the same objective as natural evolution. Natural biochemical pathways are optimized through evolution for their ability to adapt and not necessarily for a particular function, as is typically required for industrial applications. In addition, pathways often carry an evolutionary burden. Thus, design for industrial applications cannot borrow blindly from natural biochemical pathways. It is notable that robustness in the context of industrial applications does not have the same meaning as robustness with respect to environmental release. For example, biofuel production [24] typically takes place in an industrial reactor, and the primary robustness issue is to maximize the fuel yield in the presence of varying food quality. In this example, the synthetic organisms do not interact with the environment in the same way as do synthetic organisms designed for other tasks, hence the importance of robustness to that uncertainty is not as high. …robustness in the context of industrial applications does not have the same meaning as robustness with respect to environmental release Some of the most challenging problems for optimizing synthetic biology applications are those that try to blend network topology optimization with network flux optimization. Work towards this goal is described in [25], in which pathway optimization is carried out on a case-by-case basis. At the other end of the spectrum, the authors in [26] explicitly take into account optimization through pathway evolution, in a general mathematical and computational framework. Both approaches promise interesting and diverse solution strategies. In spite of these fundamentally difficult engineering challenges, there have been several industrial-scale success stories. For example, the modification of natural biochemical pathways has been used for the production of heterologous proteins [25]. Similar applications for waste degradation [15] and biofuels [27] are under development. One of the biggest successes so far has come from Jay Keasling's lab at the University of California, Berkley, USA, which focuses on improving the production of the anti-malarial drug artemisinin [28]. The plant gene amorphadiene synthase (ADS) was introduced into a re-engineered native biochemical pathway of S. cerevisiae to achieve a high yield of artemisinin with low resource consumption. The promise to provide a cheap anti-malarial drug in developing nations constitutes a significant step in demonstrating the benefits of synthetic biology, to a potentially sceptical public. From an environmental perspective, metabolic engineering has been successful in producing polylactic acid (PLA). PLA is a thermoplastic with many favourable properties: it is biodegradable, biocompatible and has low toxicity for humans. Furthermore, it is synthesized from renewable resources such as starch and sugar cane. Recent work [29] followed a full synthetic biology design cycle, including computational analysis and full genome-wide flux analysis, to develop a metabolic pathway that was inserted into E. coli. The authors knocked out unnecessary genes and were able to achieve an 11wt% increase in PLA synthesis from glucose, and up to 56wt% increase in its copolymers. As with artemisinin, these industrial examples offer much needed solutions to major societal challenges, and are a key ingredient in the necessary public engagement. Slightly outside our definition of synthetic biology, another industrial scale success took place in 2010. The Cayman Islands Mosquito Research and Control Unit in collaboration with Oxitec announced the results of a large field trial, during which approximately 3 million genetically modified (GM) mosquitos were released with the objective of reducing the population of the mosquito Aedes aegypti, a vector of the dengue virus. In this instance the A. aegypti population dropped by 80% [30]. The approach involved the ‘sterile insect technique’ [31] and a method from molecular biology known as ‘release of insects carrying a dominant lethal’ (RIDL) to ensure the syntheticpopulation died out over time [32]. The ability to create synthetic organisms, combined with our inability to control them with solid guarantees, raises the need to consider the ethical implications. Many of these issues are not new and have been addressed in many areas of life science research. We therefore particularly address the ethical considerations that relate to the introduction of synthetic organisms to the environment and describe a possible decision-making framework. Among the most commonly raised ethical issues are those focusing on the potential for synthetic biologists to create life or concerns about ‘playing God’ [33]. Counterarguments specific to synthetic biology have been made by Douglas and Savulescu [34]. Another primary concern focuses on the fact that reductionist approaches to synthetic biology might erode the distinction between organisms and machines. Further issues concern the moral status of synthetic organisms in relation to natural living organisms and non-living matter [35]. However, in our view, the ethical issues that most warrant consideration relate to the possible risks of releasing synthetic entities into the environment, given that predicting their future behaviour is a challenging task. Whilst this should motivate synthetic biologists to improve design techniques, ethical analysis might help determine what level of predictability should be required, and how the possible risks should be weighed against probable benefits. It is of paramount importance that designs should behave and evolve in a predictable manner. However, achieving perfect predictability and controllability is difficult. Thus, it is important to determine what risks are acceptable for releasing synthetic organisms into the environment. One approach to deal with risk has been the precautionary principle, which has been used in areas as diverse as climate change, ozone depletion, nanotechnology and GM crops. There are differing formulations of the precautionary principle [36,37], but a theme common to many of these is that one should exercise caution, or even refrain f" @default.
- W2004336532 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W2004336532 creator A5012634256 @default.
- W2004336532 creator A5018300444 @default.
- W2004336532 creator A5034001390 @default.
- W2004336532 creator A5042190824 @default.
- W2004336532 creator A5053811056 @default.
- W2004336532 creator A5058010593 @default.
- W2004336532 creator A5086007559 @default.
- W2004336532 date "2012-06-15" @default.
- W2004336532 modified "2023-10-09" @default.
- W2004336532 title "Engineering and ethical perspectives in synthetic biology" @default.
- W2004336532 cites W1637936532 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W1643550806 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W1965409125 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W1970743380 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W1980635471 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W1984248485 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2003609835 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2035506275 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2041042514 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2041985017 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2047767231 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2053717739 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2068270562 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2068602646 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2068747510 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2073082407 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2076367743 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2078508078 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2089617084 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2115512200 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2123794239 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2130912501 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2132109001 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2132207273 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2133091545 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2143819593 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2148471367 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2149202606 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2153624566 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2165526493 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W2166499263 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W3102206939 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W3103886388 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W4241512701 @default.
- W2004336532 cites W87882268 @default.
- W2004336532 doi "https://doi.org/10.1038/embor.2012.81" @default.
- W2004336532 hasPubMedCentralId "https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/3389334" @default.
- W2004336532 hasPubMedId "https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/22699939" @default.
- W2004336532 hasPublicationYear "2012" @default.
- W2004336532 type Work @default.
- W2004336532 sameAs 2004336532 @default.
- W2004336532 citedByCount "39" @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322012 @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322013 @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322014 @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322015 @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322016 @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322017 @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322018 @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322019 @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322020 @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322021 @default.
- W2004336532 countsByYear W20043365322023 @default.
- W2004336532 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2004336532 hasAuthorship W2004336532A5012634256 @default.
- W2004336532 hasAuthorship W2004336532A5018300444 @default.
- W2004336532 hasAuthorship W2004336532A5034001390 @default.
- W2004336532 hasAuthorship W2004336532A5042190824 @default.
- W2004336532 hasAuthorship W2004336532A5053811056 @default.
- W2004336532 hasAuthorship W2004336532A5058010593 @default.
- W2004336532 hasAuthorship W2004336532A5086007559 @default.
- W2004336532 hasBestOaLocation W20043365321 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConcept C127413603 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConcept C191908910 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConcept C55587333 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConcept C70721500 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConcept C86803240 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConcept C95124753 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConceptScore W2004336532C127413603 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConceptScore W2004336532C138885662 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConceptScore W2004336532C191908910 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConceptScore W2004336532C55587333 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConceptScore W2004336532C70721500 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConceptScore W2004336532C86803240 @default.
- W2004336532 hasConceptScore W2004336532C95124753 @default.
- W2004336532 hasIssue "7" @default.
- W2004336532 hasLocation W20043365321 @default.
- W2004336532 hasLocation W20043365322 @default.
- W2004336532 hasLocation W20043365323 @default.
- W2004336532 hasLocation W20043365324 @default.
- W2004336532 hasLocation W20043365325 @default.
- W2004336532 hasOpenAccess W2004336532 @default.
- W2004336532 hasPrimaryLocation W20043365321 @default.
- W2004336532 hasRelatedWork W2036228067 @default.
- W2004336532 hasRelatedWork W2037630877 @default.