Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2008368049> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 49 of
49
with 100 items per page.
- W2008368049 endingPage "52" @default.
- W2008368049 startingPage "51" @default.
- W2008368049 abstract "B. Vogelstein and coauthors (“Please don't call it cloning!,” Policy Forum, 15 Feb., p. [1237][1]) suggest that the term “nuclear transplantation” should be used for “somatic cell nuclear transfer to create stem cells.” The use of the term in this context was preempted some 45 years ago to mean a process that leads to cloning—precisely what Vogelstein et al. are trying to avoid! The studies by King and Briggs ([1][2]) and Gurdon ([2][3]) on amphibia are described as nuclear transplantation and remain the classic examples that have been included in numerous textbooks ranging from the second edition of Srb et al. ([3][4]) through Suzuki et al. ([4][5]) to Campbell and Reece ([5][6]). Although most of these texts concentrate on the totipotency of the nuclei transferred, some emphasize [e.g., ([4][5])] that it is the production of series of clones of the original individuals that shows the ultimate success of the nuclear transplantation process. Thus, generations of biology students will immediately think of cloning regardless of the context in which “nuclear transplantation” is used.1. [↵][7]1. T. J. King, 2. R. Briggs , Cold Spring Harbor Symp. Quant. Biol. 21, 279 (1956). [OpenUrl][8]2. [↵][9]1. J. B. Gurdon , Q. Rev. Biol. 38, 54 (1963). [OpenUrl][10][CrossRef][11][Web of Science][12]3. [↵][13]1. A. M. Srb, 2. R. D. Owen, 3. R. S. Edgar , General Genetics, ed. 2 (Freeman, San Francisco, 1966). 4. [↵][14]1. D. T. Suzuki, 2. A. J. F. Griffiths, 3. R. C. Lewontin , An Introduction to Genetic Analysis, ed. 2 (Freeman, San Francisco, 1981). 5. [↵][15]1. N. A. Campbell, 2. J. B. Reece , Biology, ed. 6 (Benjamin Cummings, Menlo Park, CA, 2002). # {#article-title-2}Vogelstein et al. subscribe to the widely held belief that a human being at an early developmental stage does not qualify as human. Certainly, we can all agree that a preimplantation embryo is not sentient and that it is not viable to survive without assistance. But making distinctions about the “humanness” of genetically human organisms on the basis of their developmental stage falls within the realm of opinion, not scientific fact.Regardless of what opinions are popularly held by members of the scientific community, we need to be careful to preserve the distinction between opinion and fact. An opinion held on a matter of philosophy by a majority of scientists is, nonetheless, an opinion, and is not brought any closer to the realm of testable fact by virtue of being held by highly regarded profesionals.Vogelstein et al. write “Both of these research goals [“creating stem cells with the patient's own nuclear genome” “Both of these research goals [“creating stem cells with the patient's own nuclear genome” “Both of these research goals [“creating stem cells with the patient's own nuclear genome” “Both of these research goals [“creating stem cells with the patient's own nuclear genome” “Both of these research goals [“creating stem cells with the patient's own nuclear genome” “Both of these research goals [“creating stem cells with the patient's own nuclear genome” “Both of these research goals [“creating stem cells with the patient's own nuclear genome” “Both of these research goals [“creating stem cells with the patient's own nuclear genome” “Both of these research goals [“creating stem cells with the patient's own nuclear genome” and “creating stem cell lines by using the somatic cell nuclei of individuals with heritable diseases”] have nothing to do with producing a human being.” On the contrary, both do indeed involve creating a human being. The authors suggest that certain avenues of research would wrongly be caught by a matter of semantics in legislation, because of the inclusion of the word “cloning”; I argue that such legislation would quite intentionally catch these avenues of research, and it is in fact their assertion that these studies would not involve production of human beings that is relying on semantics to justify its exclusion from these regulations.Supporting stem cell research and holding to philosophical distinctions between the rights of human beings from different developmental stages are quite a different thing from arguing that human embryos are not human. Our cause is only weakened by relying on such arguments to support it.# Response {#article-title-3}We thank Jones for the historical context. We can think of no one better to emulate than King, Briggs, and Gurdon, who have contributed so many elegant studies to modern embryology. “Nuclear transplantation” was a good term when they coined it, and it remains good. It is far more accurate than “therapeutic cloning” and much more easily pronounceable than “somatic cell nuclear transfer.”Meyer has, unfortunately, missed the point of our Policy Forum. Human cells growing in a Petri dish are not equal to a human being. This is fact, not opinion. Cells in a Petri dish can't talk, think, move, love, laugh, or cry, to name a few of the numerous and obvious differences. Thousands of laboratories around the world already grow human cells (fibroblasts, lymphocytes, etc.) in Petri dishes. Each of these cells has the theoretical capacity to develop into a human being after experimental manipulation. The major medical goal of nuclear transplantation is to produce human cells growing in Petri dishes that can be used for regenerative medicine. The public needs to understand that there is a huge difference between such cells and an actual human being. It is important that the current confusion about these issues does not lead to a ban on the production of certain types of human cells growing in Petri dishes, precluding potential therapies for the millions of human beings who currently suffer from otherwise incurable diseases. [1]: /lookup/doi/10.1126/science.1070247 [2]: #ref-1 [3]: #ref-2 [4]: #ref-3 [5]: #ref-4 [6]: #ref-5 [7]: #xref-ref-1-1 View reference 1 in text [8]: {openurl}?query=rft.jtitle%253DCold%2BSpring%2BHarbor%2BSymp.%2BQuant.%2BBiol.%26rft.volume%253D21%26rft.spage%253D279%26rft.atitle%253DCOLD%2BSPRING%2BHARBOR%2BSYMP%2BQUANT%2BBIOL%26rft.genre%253Darticle%26rft_val_fmt%253Dinfo%253Aofi%252Ffmt%253Akev%253Amtx%253Ajournal%26ctx_ver%253DZ39.88-2004%26url_ver%253DZ39.88-2004%26url_ctx_fmt%253Dinfo%253Aofi%252Ffmt%253Akev%253Amtx%253Actx [9]: #xref-ref-2-1 View reference 2 in text [10]: {openurl}?query=rft.jtitle%253DQ.%2BRev.%2BBiol.%26rft.volume%253D38%26rft.spage%253D54%26rft_id%253Dinfo%253Adoi%252F10.1086%252F403749%26rft.genre%253Darticle%26rft_val_fmt%253Dinfo%253Aofi%252Ffmt%253Akev%253Amtx%253Ajournal%26ctx_ver%253DZ39.88-2004%26url_ver%253DZ39.88-2004%26url_ctx_fmt%253Dinfo%253Aofi%252Ffmt%253Akev%253Amtx%253Actx [11]: /lookup/external-ref?access_num=10.1086/403749&link_type=DOI [12]: /lookup/external-ref?access_num=A1963WM88900003&link_type=ISI [13]: #xref-ref-3-1 View reference 3 in text [14]: #xref-ref-4-1 View reference 4 in text [15]: #xref-ref-5-1 View reference 5 in text" @default.
- W2008368049 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W2008368049 creator A5011860432 @default.
- W2008368049 date "2002-07-05" @default.
- W2008368049 modified "2023-10-16" @default.
- W2008368049 title "Calling It Something Other Than Cloning" @default.
- W2008368049 cites W1652529314 @default.
- W2008368049 cites W1988916096 @default.
- W2008368049 cites W2094218023 @default.
- W2008368049 doi "https://doi.org/10.1126/science.297.5578.51" @default.
- W2008368049 hasPubMedId "https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/12102093" @default.
- W2008368049 hasPublicationYear "2002" @default.
- W2008368049 type Work @default.
- W2008368049 sameAs 2008368049 @default.
- W2008368049 citedByCount "0" @default.
- W2008368049 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2008368049 hasAuthorship W2008368049A5011860432 @default.
- W2008368049 hasConcept C121050878 @default.
- W2008368049 hasConcept C199360897 @default.
- W2008368049 hasConcept C41008148 @default.
- W2008368049 hasConcept C70721500 @default.
- W2008368049 hasConcept C86803240 @default.
- W2008368049 hasConceptScore W2008368049C121050878 @default.
- W2008368049 hasConceptScore W2008368049C199360897 @default.
- W2008368049 hasConceptScore W2008368049C41008148 @default.
- W2008368049 hasConceptScore W2008368049C70721500 @default.
- W2008368049 hasConceptScore W2008368049C86803240 @default.
- W2008368049 hasIssue "5578" @default.
- W2008368049 hasLocation W20083680491 @default.
- W2008368049 hasLocation W20083680492 @default.
- W2008368049 hasOpenAccess W2008368049 @default.
- W2008368049 hasPrimaryLocation W20083680491 @default.
- W2008368049 hasRelatedWork W1563774556 @default.
- W2008368049 hasRelatedWork W2025282766 @default.
- W2008368049 hasRelatedWork W2085788485 @default.
- W2008368049 hasRelatedWork W2223108609 @default.
- W2008368049 hasRelatedWork W2327056875 @default.
- W2008368049 hasRelatedWork W2352038341 @default.
- W2008368049 hasRelatedWork W2896567360 @default.
- W2008368049 hasRelatedWork W3200415547 @default.
- W2008368049 hasRelatedWork W629843366 @default.
- W2008368049 hasRelatedWork W3097729625 @default.
- W2008368049 hasVolume "297" @default.
- W2008368049 isParatext "false" @default.
- W2008368049 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W2008368049 magId "2008368049" @default.
- W2008368049 workType "article" @default.