Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2011004087> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 90 of
90
with 100 items per page.
- W2011004087 endingPage "213" @default.
- W2011004087 startingPage "189" @default.
- W2011004087 abstract "Locke, Leibniz, and the Logic of Mechanism Martha Brandt Bolton 1 early mechanist philosophers demanded a new standard of perspicuity in the natural sciences. They accused others of “explaining” phenomena in terms of obscurely defined, unconfirmed, and uninformative causes. These complaints were leveled, not just at the real qualities and forms of Scholastics, but also against the sympathetic attractions of Hermetics and the sophic principles (mercury, sulphur, salt) of the Spagyrites. These competitors to mechanism could at best demonstrate that a certain effect occurs and claim to state why it does. Mechanists aspired to explain how phenomena are produced.1 Beyond that, however, philosophers in the broadly “mechanist” movement shared no single account of what this sort of explanation involves. They were too diverse, not only in their views on the central notions of material substance, cause, and force, but also with respect to their standards of intelligibility. In this paper, however, I want to isolate one mechanist model of explanation with intellectual virtues that strongly recommended it in some quarters. I will argue specifically that it influenced Leibniz and Locke. This favored form of mechanism opens a deep problem, because it conflicts with the existence of causal interaction between bodies and minds.2 It is not just that the model does not apply beyond the realm of intercorporeal [End Page 189] phenomena, but much worse, that acceptance of mental-corporeal causality threatens to undermine the mechanist model in its most perspicuous form. The difficulty could be avoided, but by accepting a form of mechanism considerably less intellectually satisfying. The difference has to do with the metaphysical analysis of what it is for an individual to have a causal power. Hence Leibniz and Locke and perhaps others faced a dilemma: whether to affirm the more appealing version of mechanism or to affirm a mechanism that accommodates mind-body interaction. The former required one account of causal powers, the latter a significantly different one. Leibniz had reasons for affirming the more perspicuous version of mechanism and the associated account of causal powers; and he denied mind-body interaction. I intend to show that the specifically mechanist model of intelligibility plays a little noticed part in his arguments against psychophysical causality. But in this paper I will have more to say about Locke. He was convinced that we observe mind-body interaction and he gave experience the highest authority. My contention is that plain logic required him to reject the favored version of mechanism. He noted that bodies have some powers that are inconceivable to us (e.g., as he stressed, powers to cause ideas). These are powers of the sort Locke repeatedly said we can only ascribe to the good pleasure of God. There has been a protracted debate over the correct interpretation of these remarks.3 I will argue that they express Locke’s logically cogent response to the dilemma. Recognizing that mechanism cannot explain some powers bodies have, as he thought experience shows, Locke proposed that a version of mechanism might still be correct; but in that case, some corporeal powers have no intelligible means of manifestation. They operate only by “the good pleasure of God” and their conjunction with intelligible corporeal powers has the same source. But he was not so committed to any version of mechanism that he affirmed that there are unintelligible corporeal powers. There has been some interest in tracing the early modern antecedents of later views that identify causal relations with regularities or with general laws [End Page 190] that contingently govern things of the sorts they do.4 An account of the first type was later urged by Hume, whereas the second was advocated by the occasionalist, Malebranche. Neither is intelligible by the mechanist standard, which locates causality in individuals whose powers are the basis of general laws. Leibniz was able to maintain that all causes in nature are of this sort. Locke, who could not see his way clear to that, still refrained from adopting an alternative view of causality. But the difficulty psychophysical causality poses might seem to make a less realist theory attractive. 2. the favored version of mechanism The contributions to theoretical natural science made by Leibniz and Robert..." @default.
- W2011004087 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W2011004087 creator A5022921532 @default.
- W2011004087 date "1998-01-01" @default.
- W2011004087 modified "2023-10-10" @default.
- W2011004087 title "Locke, Leibniz, and the Logic of Mechanism" @default.
- W2011004087 cites W1486601011 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W1491275591 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W1538556544 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W1578724009 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W1595480604 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W1607940017 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W1766015563 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W1981789683 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2015768771 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2037412806 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2048132622 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2062248716 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2062403659 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2131999674 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2312810988 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2326417977 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2327015109 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2327743288 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2331117979 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2466732012 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2494576045 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2798422882 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W2970518777 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W3184674809 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W3207076107 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W367761691 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W645725281 @default.
- W2011004087 cites W656480199 @default.
- W2011004087 doi "https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2008.0829" @default.
- W2011004087 hasPublicationYear "1998" @default.
- W2011004087 type Work @default.
- W2011004087 sameAs 2011004087 @default.
- W2011004087 citedByCount "4" @default.
- W2011004087 countsByYear W20110040872015 @default.
- W2011004087 countsByYear W20110040872021 @default.
- W2011004087 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2011004087 hasAuthorship W2011004087A5022921532 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C121332964 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C155785087 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C166957645 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C17744445 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C199539241 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C2776608160 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C2778757428 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C62520636 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C64357122 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C89611455 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConcept C95457728 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C111472728 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C121332964 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C138885662 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C155785087 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C166957645 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C17744445 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C199539241 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C2776608160 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C2778757428 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C62520636 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C64357122 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C89611455 @default.
- W2011004087 hasConceptScore W2011004087C95457728 @default.
- W2011004087 hasIssue "2" @default.
- W2011004087 hasLocation W20110040871 @default.
- W2011004087 hasOpenAccess W2011004087 @default.
- W2011004087 hasPrimaryLocation W20110040871 @default.
- W2011004087 hasRelatedWork W1557853388 @default.
- W2011004087 hasRelatedWork W2027529004 @default.
- W2011004087 hasRelatedWork W2067510282 @default.
- W2011004087 hasRelatedWork W2359053655 @default.
- W2011004087 hasRelatedWork W2362511569 @default.
- W2011004087 hasRelatedWork W2382709029 @default.
- W2011004087 hasRelatedWork W2387777532 @default.
- W2011004087 hasRelatedWork W2502221315 @default.
- W2011004087 hasRelatedWork W2506029534 @default.
- W2011004087 hasRelatedWork W2973036681 @default.
- W2011004087 hasVolume "36" @default.
- W2011004087 isParatext "false" @default.
- W2011004087 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W2011004087 magId "2011004087" @default.
- W2011004087 workType "article" @default.