Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2016141310> ?p ?o ?g. }
- W2016141310 endingPage "2471" @default.
- W2016141310 startingPage "2467" @default.
- W2016141310 abstract "The concepts of ethnicity, ancestry, and race are widely used in molecular epidemiologic research, often based on the assumption that these correlate (however roughly) with increased genetic homogeneity among people claiming a similar identity. However, some have questioned the implications of research on ethnic or racial differences, particularly in the area of health disparities research (1, 2). This emphasis may lead to an overly simplistic attribution of poor health to biological rather than social or political factors (3, 4). Thus, a danger of the use of genetics as a major determinant of health and health disparities is that stereotypes of health and disease in certain groups may be perpetuated and alternative solutions to these problems will be ignored. Similarly, others have postulated that self-identified race or ethnicity (SIRE) is primarily sociocultural rather than biological and their use in genetic research is invalid (5, 6). Some argue that ethnicity is built of social, legal, and historical factors and bears no necessary or predictable relationship to genetic factors (7, 8).To theorists who eschew SIRE as a biological concept, its function as a variable is to capture predictable dimensions of a person's or a group's daily experience that are tied to shared beliefs and practices. Beliefs (and practices based on those beliefs) might include what people hold true about themselves as members of a recognized group. For example, researchers may capture an individual respondent's notion of belonging to a group, such as “As a member of group A, I prefer these foods.” Those who define SIRE as a social construct grant that there might be biological consequences of membership in these groups, such as result from diet or family size, but the consequences, without basis in genetics, are mutable and transient. According to this thinking, membership and boundaries of SIRE groups evolve over time, reflecting and influencing political and cultural events. This notion is supported by a study reporting that one third of individuals asked to assign themselves to an ethnic group in 2 consecutive years chose a different ethnic group in the second year (9). Thus, to social constructionists, ethnicity labeled “self-identified” would have to be spontaneously named by a subject and could not be assumed to have genetic correlates.In contrast, population and evolutionary genetics research has examined genetic variability within and between members of SIRE groups. For example, the FST statistic of Wright (10) has been used as a measure of subdivision within species, where FST = 100% suggests that genomic variability is completely between groups (i.e., the groups are genetically distinct) and FST = 0% suggests the absence of genetically distinct groups with all of the observed genomic variability occurring within populations. Using large-scale genomic information, the average value of FST in humans has been estimated to be ∼13% (11). Although there is significant variability in the value of FST across the human genome, FST = 13% supports the existence of between-group genomic differences, but does not indicate that SIRE groups are genomically distinct. Nonetheless, biological correlates of self-identified race or ethnicity exist. Numerous large-scale genomic studies have reported that the observed distribution of allelic variation in the human genome differs among groups. Although most genetic variation is common to all populations, genetic variants exist that are unique to specific SIRE groups (12). Using a genetic-cluster analysis algorithm to group individuals based on their genetic marker information alone, Tang et al. (13) reported that among 3,636 participants from four multicenter studies of blood pressure using 326 microsatellite linkage markers, only 17 individuals (0.5%) did not cluster according to SIRE. Although these results are striking, the analyses did not consider admixture within populations and thus overemphasized the distinctions between SIRE groups. Nonetheless, these and other data support the notion that correlations between genomic variability and SIRE exist, and thus refute those who reject any genetic basis to race or ethnicity.These constructs are apparently at odds with one another and emphasize the need to define carefully and use appropriately the concepts of race, ancestry, or ethnicity in molecular epidemiologic research. We propose that it is not productive to continue the debate about whether racial or ethnic groups do or do not have genomic correlates. Rather, the need is to recognize that multiple, distinct concepts of race or ethnicity exist, and to move molecular epidemiologic research toward effectively characterizing and using these.Because SIRE can be correlated with both biological and sociocultural phenomena, models that consider only one of these explanations are ineffective for molecular epidemiologic research. Thus, we consider group membership as a complex, multifactorial trait similar to height, blood pressure, intelligence, or common disease phenotypes. Figure 1 suggests a framework for considering SIRE that includes both biological phenomena as well as environmental and sociocultural differences that modify the relationship between genotype and phenotypes. These categories are observational and relational. They are observational in the sense that their component features are those that interest molecular epidemiology rather than those that group members might cite. These component features might overlap with features that group members cite but the premise for emphasizing these features is their relevance to research rather than to social identity. These categories are relational in that they are meaningful only in the context of specific comparisons and are not discrete entities that stand alone outside a particular research context. For example, genomically similar groups that are culturally dissimilar may represent major or minor comparisons between ethnic groups, depending on the context of the research question.We use the generic term “group” to denote self-identified group membership. “Biological inheritance” denotes those innate factors that capture information about genomic variability and historical events, such as migration or selection, that have influenced the current patterns of genomic variation. Biological inheritance is correlated with phenotypes that in part define the physical features associated with SIRE. These phenotypes include skin color, hair type, facial features such as eye shape or nasal bridge structure, and body habitus. These phenotypes can be further correlated with group membership. The strength of the correlation between biological inheritance and phenotype and between phenotype and group can also be influenced by an individual's environment, including exposures such as diet, lifestyle, occupation, or residence. Finally, the relationship between phenotype and group is further influenced by cultural factors such as religion, language, and social customs.The use of ethnicity, ancestry, or race in molecular epidemiologic research is to account for differences that reflect etiologic or prognostic differences or to ameliorate study biases. Assuming that we can identify features that allow us to define group differences in epidemiologic research (i.e., ancestry, culture, environment, and phenotype; Fig. 1), we attempt to construct concepts of ethnicity, ancestry, or race that can serve research effectively and which recognize and benefit from the complexity inherent to these concepts. To this end, we define four general terms that may be used when comparing groups of individuals. These do not represent discrete categorizations but are landmarks on a continuum (Fig. 2).“Minor ethnicity” refers to locally constituted (i.e., physically proximal) groups who think of their members as similar to one another and distinct from neighboring groups (other minor ethnicities), although these different groups share many genomic, cultural, and environmental factors in common. The actual cultural or environmental differences between groups distinguished as different minor ethnic groups may be negligible and arbitrary, particularly if ethnic labels have been assigned by outsiders without reference to differences that might be recognizable to members of those groups. Alternatively, these differences may be apparent to both group members and outsiders (7). The Nuer and the Dinka of East Africa are examples of minor ethnicities. Although minor ethnic groups are similar in many ways, differences in diet, reproductive patterns, or other behaviors may influence disease.“Major ethnicity” can be used to contrast groups that share some degree of common ancestry, but have diverged to some degree in terms of culture (e.g., language, religion) and environment. Natives of various European countries or the peoples of Northeast Asia are examples of major ethnicities. There is generally no presumed major genomic basis for differences among these groups.“Ancestry” can be used to define comparisons of groups that are genomically divergent, but share cultural or environmental similarities. An example of ancestral groupings includes African Americans and European Americans, who share many common cultural and environmental characteristics, but diverge in terms of their genomic (geographic) ancestry.“Race” can be used to characterize comparisons of groups that diverge in most respects. For example, Native Australian Aboriginals and East Asians share relatively fewer genomic, cultural, or environmental characteristics.This proposed nosology is meant to help to organize thinking rather than to represent a fixed underlying axis of differentiation among human groups. As in any attempt to define such complex concepts, numerous caveats must be considered. The components of the frameworks in Figs. 1 and 2 are potential, but not required, influences in determining group boundaries. To emphasize the point that these definitions are arbitrary and meant to depict a continuum to be used to conduct research, we point out that narrowly defined groups (minor ethnicities) may still constitute “racial” comparisons if they are sufficiently distinct in terms of genomic, cultural, and environmental characteristics (e.g., African Nuer versus Italian Calabrians). The same subjects could fall into different groups in different research projects. Cosenzans compared with other Calabrians may represent minor ethnicity comparisons (14). If Calabrians and Cosenzans were contrasted with Scandinavians, the internal distinctions disappear and both Calabrians and Cosenzans would become Southern Italian, members of a major ethnicity. In yet another project, distinctions among these populations might be submerged and the group as a whole is treated as European and contrasted with African as a racial comparison. An additional caution is to remain aware that, for historical and social reasons, some populations will fit more easily into certain categories. For example, the differences between Sicilians and Swedes seem relatively easy to characterize. However, comparisons of Puerto Ricans and Mexican Americans, or between Hispanic Americans and Non-Hispanic European Americans are complex, with the former not clearly a minor ethnicity nor a major ethnicity and the latter arguably definable as either major ethnicity or ancestry. Using this framework, the ease or difficulty with which labels can be assigned to research populations or populations can be assigned to categories is understood as an artifact of a particular research question rather than a feature of the group.Given the many concerns about the meaning and use of ethnicity, ancestry, or race in epidemiologic research, why would a molecular epidemiologist choose to include these concepts in their research? As outlined below, study bias or inefficiencies may result if these concepts are ignored.Ethnicity, ancestry, or race can serve as surrogate measures to identify high-risk groups. Groups that have a particularly high incidence or strong familial aggregation of disease may represent an optimal resource in which to identify or characterize disease genes. For some diseases or traits, increased incidence or aggregation may identify exposed-predisposed groups. This is likely to be the case in diseases with a complex, multifactorial etiology caused by the interaction of inherited genotypes and exposures. Similarly, those prone to poor treatment response or increased toxicities also represent “high-risk” groups that may be, in part, determined by their genome. Although it has been proposed that treatment may be based on ethnicity alone (15), it is likely that ethnic-specific differences in treatment response are in fact determined by specific metabolic genotypes, the frequency of which may vary by ethnicity. Thus, the field of pharmacogenetics is likely to contribute to improved individual-specific, rather than race-specific, treatment.Because geography and migration histories of populations share sufficient overlap with socially constructed categories of race or ethnicity, socially constructed categories have been widely used as an index of genetic homogeneity. Because exposures are fundamentally shaped by social environments, ethnicity, ancestry, and race may be used to operationalize different experiences of exposure. Most common diseases and phenotypes are under the influence of numerous etiologic agents, including both genes and environmental exposures. To the extent that socially defined ethnicity and allele frequencies are similarly patterned, choosing subjects by ethnicity may affect the genetic homogeneity of a study population. Gene identification studies have been proposed that specifically use admixed populations (e.g., mapping by admixture linkage disequilibrium; ref. 16). Similarly, founder mutations that occur in specific (usually culturally or geographically isolated) populations provide an opportunity to study homogeneous subgroups (e.g., French Canadians, Icelanders, and Ashkenazi Jews). For example, common founder mutations in the BRCA1 and BRCA2 genes in Jewish populations simplify genetic testing for clinical risk assessment and identify a relatively common limited set of background mutations in which to better understand BRCA1- and BRCA2-associated carcinogenesis.Appropriate study sample size and power are critical aspects of all epidemiologic studies. Power is dependent on the frequency of the exposure or genotype being studied. Because genotype frequencies tend to vary by ethnicity, ancestry, or race, studies may have inadequate power or may be inefficient (i.e., using larger sample sizes than may be necessary) if race- or ethnicity-specific estimates of genotype or exposure frequencies are not considered. Similarly, genome scans that use concepts of linkage and linkage disequilibrium may suffer if ethnicity is not properly considered. Genome-wide association or linkage methods are dependent on the linkage disequilibrium among genetic variants on a chromosome. Differences in the pattern of linkage disequilibrium by race have been reported (17); this could affect the success of gene discovery efforts.Numerous authors have examined the implications of unrecognized population structure to induce bias, false-positive associations, and lack of replication in association studies (18-28). Population stratification (i.e., confounding by ethnicity) can occur if both baseline disease risks and risk-conferring allele frequencies differ across the groups being studied (e.g., races or ethnicities). If either of these criteria is not fulfilled, this bias cannot occur. Although there are numerous examples of genotype frequency differences by ethnicity and disease risk differences by ethnicity, the evidence to date suggests that potential biases are small if baseline disease or allele frequency differences between ethnicities are small, diminish as admixture increases (e.g., if the number of component ethnicities is large, as may be the case in African Americans; refs. 24, 29), and may be more pronounced in recently admixed populations (30). However, it is also clear that population structure can be observed even in apparently homogeneous populations (31). Thus, a variety of methods have been proposed to correct for the biases that may result from these ethnic or ethnic differences, including the use of multiple unlinked markers to correct for or quantify potential biases (19, 32) or study designs that address potential bias by using relatives or matching strategies (33, 34).The literature to date indicates that potential biases can be corrected for by the usual methods of statistical adjustment in study samples comprised of widely divergent races or may be unnecessary in genomically homogeneous populations (e.g., Northern Europeans; refs. 29, 30). However, studies of admixed populations (e.g., African Americans) represent a more complex situation. Millikan (35) reported that a minimal bias in point estimates was observed in African American populations. Ardlie et al. (30) observed the potential for population structure to exist in African American populations, but also that this structure was reduced by removing recent African or Caribbean immigrants. Wang et al. (24) used simulation data that infer that odds ratios in association studies of unrelated African Americans would not be markedly distorted even under conditions of extreme differences in baseline disease risk and genotype frequency in the component admixed populations. Nonetheless, despite the limited evidence that population stratification causes biases to estimates in most common situations, it is clear that ignoring ethnicity in molecular epidemiologic studies can lead to some distortion of estimates of association. Therefore, all studies should carefully consider the potential for confounding by ethnicity, ancestry, or race, and respond with appropriate study design or analytic methods (28).Although there are concerns about the use of ethnicity, ancestry, or race in molecular epidemiologic research, this information may prove valuable or necessary to achieve meaningful study results. Proper consideration of these concepts should be made in the early stages of research. Thus, molecular epidemiologic researchers must consider the proper use and context when applying ethnicity, ancestry, or race to ensure that these concepts enhance the value of research and do not undermine the translation of this research to improved human health.Despite the widespread use of ethnicity, ancestry, or race in certain kinds of genetic research, details on how these concepts are defined or used are often sparse in the literature: Authors sometimes neglect to define the terms or to explain how labels were chosen or assigned to subjects. Similarly, different approaches are used in creating these definitions. For example, Tang et al. (13) relied on self-identified ethnicity; however, two study sites asked participants to choose one SIRE from among the four to seven provided by researchers; a third allowed participants to self-describe without a list of choices but then recorded all responses as “other” that did not correspond to Caucasian/White or African American. In certain analyses, those who identified themselves as “other” were excluded. The fourth site required participants to self-describe as either Chinese or Japanese and to identify four grandparents as either Chinese or Japanese. Although all of these procedures allowed subjects to choose their preferred SIRE, they also limited the categories with which subjects could identify. Operationalizing SIRE in this way is standard and, in itself, poses no threat to conclusions. However, these points emphasize how differently researchers may conceptualize ethnicity.Most studies make use of a fairly crude measure of ethnicity, ancestry, or race that may not fully reflect group membership as a complex trait. Thus, although self-identified race or ethnicity may capture some of the relevant genetic, cultural, environmental, or phenotypic influences that determine group membership, it is likely to be an inherently misclassified measure of the true quantity of interest.The effect of variable misclassification in epidemiologic research is well known and may lead to biases of various types. In the context of a (nested) case-control study design, a nondifferentially misclassified variable can lead to bias toward the null hypothesis. If used as a confounder, a misclassified variable will be less likely to account for confounding in the relationship between the risk factor of interest and disease risk. If the misclassification is differential, as might be expected if the relationship of a genotype and disease differed between ethnic groups and between cases and controls, the direction and magnitude of bias are unpredictable and could include bias of estimates either toward or away from the null hypothesis. Furthermore, coding of a self-identified ethnicity variable may lead to additional modeling errors in addition to misclassification. For example, if self-identified ethnicity is coded for analysis as an ordered discrete variable (e.g., 0 = European, 1 = African, 2 = Asian), this ordering of an otherwise unordered variable may cause inferential errors.Like many other variables, the analytic variable describing ethnicity, ancestry, or race should be constructed with regard to the specific research setting and hypotheses. As described above, self-identified group membership can be thought of as a complex continuously distributed variable under the influence of multiple factors, including genes, culture, and environment. By analogy, studies of hypertension may consider blood pressure as a continuous trait or may use hypertension as a discrete outcome. Continuous blood pressure measurements capture the complex distribution of this trait and may better reflect multiple exposures and genetic influences at a given point in time or under a specific circumstance. However, this measure may also be biased if, for example, some study subjects were taking antihypertensive medication. If so, the continuous blood pressure measurement may not reflect a relevant biological entity, and a binary variable such as “hypertensive” versus “normotensive” may be more valid. Similarly, the use of ethnicity, ancestry, or race may be best defined by a more complex composite (and possibly semicontinuous or continuous) variable in some research settings but may be more appropriate as a discrete variable with relatively few levels for other research questions. Recent studies of genomic markers have opened the door to purely genomic definitions of these concepts (36).The absence of detail and consistency about how ethnicity, ancestry, or race are defined may affect replicability or comparability of studies and leaves the field vulnerable to complaints that its use of the terms meant to capture ethnicity, ancestry, or race is not scientifically adequate (37-39). Several journals request detailed information and standardization in papers that use concepts of ethnicity, ancestry, or race in genetics research (40, 41). To those, we add the following considerations:Researchers should consider the use of these concepts before analysis. For example, is race being included out of habit as a baseline demographic variable? Is this information needed to test proposed hypotheses? Alternatively, if the concepts are being used as proxies for something else, can improved measures be developed? For example, would socioeconomic status provide a better measure of potential confounding than self-identified race?Much of the persistent controversy over the use of the terms “ethnicity,” “ancestry,” or “race” may attributable to the imprecision of their use. Ideally, the definition and use of these terms in different settings will share common features. It behooves users to explain their definitions of the meaning of these variables, not as general concepts, but making clear the particular way they are using them. For example, an appropriate concept for some genetics studies may be to consider the term “ancestry” (Figs. 1 and 2), which can capture concepts of genomic variation, biology, or geographic history. Studies may also use ethnicity to refer to regulatory or bureaucratic categories or to social identity as in aspects of access to health care that might relate to discrimination. These specific situations should be described to clarify meaning and use.Several attempts to address the debate about ethnicity, ancestry, or race in genetics have been made. Some disciplines have proposed new terminology as a solution, thus there are many terms from which to choose. These include many questionable neologisms such as macroethnicities or “race/ethnicity” (42). The enormous variation in terms used today suggests that standardized terminology is not helpful and that a careful explanation of how and why one is using a specific term is likely to be the most appropriate approach. Criteria used to decide what term(s) best fit the proposed use might include prior practice in the literature, labels preferred by study participants, or categories that match important databases.Adhere to the chosen term or terms and vary terms only when there is different meaning that needs to be conveyed. If there is a different meaning to convey, consider a brief explanation in the text as to why was required.Epidemiologic studies attempting to identify or characterize disease genes almost always use socially constructed measures of ethnicity, ancestry, or race. These measures may have utility in increasing study efficiency or reducing confounding. However, an important future direction for research will be to develop new measures that correlate with SIRE that may better reflect the complex nature of this variable." @default.
- W2016141310 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W2016141310 creator A5074868327 @default.
- W2016141310 creator A5087943563 @default.
- W2016141310 date "2005-11-01" @default.
- W2016141310 modified "2023-10-15" @default.
- W2016141310 title "Ethnicity, Ancestry, and Race in Molecular Epidemiologic Research" @default.
- W2016141310 cites W1562813268 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W1830283192 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W1888224382 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W1975365488 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W1975878048 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W1982663312 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W1986265706 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W1986652078 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2002395285 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2003073123 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2007480015 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2008047653 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2009144436 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2018965136 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2026298984 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2056946864 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2065164285 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2072100938 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2073655620 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2083248227 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2083910374 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2091341519 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2098980155 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2108491786 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2109932150 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2110871641 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2112012507 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2115449411 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2116329478 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2120483845 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2141042406 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2143249342 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2156685906 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2160514929 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W2505296838 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W3123938274 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W4230187346 @default.
- W2016141310 cites W4236770088 @default.
- W2016141310 doi "https://doi.org/10.1158/1055-9965.epi-05-0649" @default.
- W2016141310 hasPubMedId "https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/16284364" @default.
- W2016141310 hasPublicationYear "2005" @default.
- W2016141310 type Work @default.
- W2016141310 sameAs 2016141310 @default.
- W2016141310 citedByCount "41" @default.
- W2016141310 countsByYear W20161413102012 @default.
- W2016141310 countsByYear W20161413102013 @default.
- W2016141310 countsByYear W20161413102014 @default.
- W2016141310 countsByYear W20161413102016 @default.
- W2016141310 countsByYear W20161413102017 @default.
- W2016141310 countsByYear W20161413102019 @default.
- W2016141310 countsByYear W20161413102021 @default.
- W2016141310 countsByYear W20161413102022 @default.
- W2016141310 countsByYear W20161413102023 @default.
- W2016141310 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2016141310 hasAuthorship W2016141310A5074868327 @default.
- W2016141310 hasAuthorship W2016141310A5087943563 @default.
- W2016141310 hasBestOaLocation W20161413101 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C137403100 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C144024400 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C19165224 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C205649164 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C2908647359 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C59822182 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C71924100 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C75069973 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C76509639 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C86803240 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConcept C99454951 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C137403100 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C144024400 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C19165224 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C205649164 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C2908647359 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C59822182 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C71924100 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C75069973 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C76509639 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C86803240 @default.
- W2016141310 hasConceptScore W2016141310C99454951 @default.
- W2016141310 hasIssue "11" @default.
- W2016141310 hasLocation W20161413101 @default.
- W2016141310 hasLocation W20161413102 @default.
- W2016141310 hasOpenAccess W2016141310 @default.
- W2016141310 hasPrimaryLocation W20161413101 @default.
- W2016141310 hasRelatedWork W1995515455 @default.
- W2016141310 hasRelatedWork W2011988460 @default.
- W2016141310 hasRelatedWork W2080531066 @default.
- W2016141310 hasRelatedWork W2153944371 @default.
- W2016141310 hasRelatedWork W2248612747 @default.
- W2016141310 hasRelatedWork W2748952813 @default.
- W2016141310 hasRelatedWork W2899084033 @default.