Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2050894839> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 100 of
100
with 100 items per page.
- W2050894839 endingPage "85" @default.
- W2050894839 startingPage "57" @default.
- W2050894839 abstract "Gentiles of the Soul:Maximus the Confessor on the Substructure and Transformation of the Human Passions Paul M. Blowers (bio) Abstract Maximus the Confessor, in his attempt to deal with the problems of human passion, freedom, and love in an ontological and physiological as well as moral framework, is seen by some scholars to be adumbrating the thought of Aquinas on these subjects. Yet the argument here is that Maximus's doctrine of the human passions is aimed not per se at a comprehensive metaphysics of human passibility or at a doctrine of supernaturally infused [inline-graphic xmlns:xlink=http://www.w3.org/1999/xlink xlink:href=01i/], but—still very much in a neo-Cappadocian (and to some degree neo-Areopagitic) key—at a teleology of the passions that judges their ultimate ontological status in relation to the latent chaotic element in bodily nature, the definition of the frontiers of human freedom, and the ongoing, ever-unfolding potentiality, resourcefulness, and moral-spiritual utility of all natural human faculties. All of this belongs, moreover, within Maximus's larger Christological perspective. As the gentiles of the soul, to use Maximus's own analogy, the passions are a contingent presence in the history of human nature, and despite their deviance in connection with the abuse of free will, they still constitute a crucial vehicle by which incarnational grace is embodied in the farthest reaches of the cosmic order, of which human nature is the treasured microcosm. In classical philosophy as well as later patristic thought, the human passions presented a moral but inevitably also an ontological, or else physiological, dilemma. Plato debated in his dialogues over whether the soul's lower, passible parts had any real (eternal) existence apart from incarnation and involvement with evil. But neither he, nor Aristotle after him, could ultimately imagine the soul moving without some measure of passion, and in the Republic and the Symposium he saw desire () [End Page 57] and irascibility (), right along with ruling reason, as manifestations or functions of the soul's essential energy of , the deep passion propelling it toward things divine.1 For these classical writers, as Martha Nussbaum suggests, the passions are not simply the blind surges of affect nor equatable with appetites like hunger and thirst; they have to do with the determination of the Good and actually embody ways of interpreting the world.2 The Stoics, while generally convinced that pleasure, pain, fear, desire and other passions were not rooted in parts of the soul but were errant mental impulses (), judgments (), or opinions (), perhaps associated with diseased states or dispositions of the mind, were neither univocal nor transparently clear on the ontology of the passions within the dominion of the mind ().3 Yet in [End Page 58] their idealization of as the complete conquest of the passions, Stoic writers retreated from a purely nihilistic position: utter destruction of affectivity would be unwise, indeed unintelligible. The true goal of the moral life would rather be a therapeutic affectivity, wherein certain —not good passions as such but trained, reasonable affective responses—would displace irrational or diseased ones and bring stability to the soul.4 In turn, the perceived latitude for interpreting the precise ontology of the passions inevitably opened a door for later Stoic writers like Posidonius to platonize the passions as faculties of the soul, and prompted a sophisticated critique from the likes of Galen.5 In time it would provide an incentive for early and medieval Christian writers to [End Page 59] make their own refinements both on the morality and the physiology of the passions. In patristic literature, evocative discussions of the human passions as a problem of philosophical psychology come not only in technical treatises of theological anthropology6 but in the ascetic and monastic tradition, where doctrine and experience constantly converge.7 To be sure, early monastic writers generally begin with the properly moral or existential dilemma of the passions, not their physiology. Evagrius sums it up this way: the ascetic life is the spiritual method for cleansing the passible part of the soul,8 the war against the wicked and idle thoughts () that induce passions and the perfection of in the interest of undistracted..." @default.
- W2050894839 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W2050894839 creator A5086256044 @default.
- W2050894839 date "1996-01-01" @default.
- W2050894839 modified "2023-10-17" @default.
- W2050894839 title "Gentiles of the Soul: Maximus the Confessor on the Substructure and Transformation of Human Passions" @default.
- W2050894839 cites W1487251541 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W1793714185 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2003305718 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2013797427 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2027699594 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2033773351 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2046715070 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2047251670 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2049742383 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2058887555 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2066061026 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2082876390 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2083264381 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2298138784 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2508287335 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2765095876 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2801758461 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2978353160 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2979686860 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W572030836 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W578006565 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W583532486 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W584013283 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W593722385 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W615231817 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W628495726 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W633711171 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W633739857 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W654267315 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W656485498 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W2035668014 @default.
- W2050894839 cites W582140029 @default.
- W2050894839 doi "https://doi.org/10.1353/earl.1996.0008" @default.
- W2050894839 hasPublicationYear "1996" @default.
- W2050894839 type Work @default.
- W2050894839 sameAs 2050894839 @default.
- W2050894839 citedByCount "34" @default.
- W2050894839 countsByYear W20508948392014 @default.
- W2050894839 countsByYear W20508948392015 @default.
- W2050894839 countsByYear W20508948392016 @default.
- W2050894839 countsByYear W20508948392017 @default.
- W2050894839 countsByYear W20508948392020 @default.
- W2050894839 countsByYear W20508948392021 @default.
- W2050894839 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2050894839 hasAuthorship W2050894839A5086256044 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C124952713 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C142362112 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C15744967 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C182744844 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C27206212 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C2776211767 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C2776347870 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C2777239683 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C2780310893 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C2780822299 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C521332185 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConcept C77805123 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C111472728 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C124952713 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C138885662 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C142362112 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C15744967 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C182744844 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C27206212 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C2776211767 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C2776347870 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C2777239683 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C2780310893 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C2780822299 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C521332185 @default.
- W2050894839 hasConceptScore W2050894839C77805123 @default.
- W2050894839 hasIssue "1" @default.
- W2050894839 hasLocation W20508948391 @default.
- W2050894839 hasOpenAccess W2050894839 @default.
- W2050894839 hasPrimaryLocation W20508948391 @default.
- W2050894839 hasRelatedWork W2108611755 @default.
- W2050894839 hasRelatedWork W2158323869 @default.
- W2050894839 hasRelatedWork W2346914283 @default.
- W2050894839 hasRelatedWork W2888275535 @default.
- W2050894839 hasRelatedWork W2890689331 @default.
- W2050894839 hasRelatedWork W2930266059 @default.
- W2050894839 hasRelatedWork W3039062629 @default.
- W2050894839 hasRelatedWork W3136399693 @default.
- W2050894839 hasRelatedWork W3157374416 @default.
- W2050894839 hasRelatedWork W647325308 @default.
- W2050894839 hasVolume "4" @default.
- W2050894839 isParatext "false" @default.
- W2050894839 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W2050894839 magId "2050894839" @default.
- W2050894839 workType "article" @default.