Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2085173615> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 40 of
40
with 100 items per page.
- W2085173615 endingPage "289" @default.
- W2085173615 startingPage "240" @default.
- W2085173615 abstract "ion from its individualization in which it exists in individuals is considered to be the signified object of a term in simple supposition. The realists, therefore, admit two formal signified objects, the individuals (and that only in personal supposition) and the common nature, and that in simple supposition. For that reason, according to them not only natural supposition is different from personal supposition, but also simple supposition, though both, natural and simple supposition exercise their significative function.38 It seems that the first clash on this score took place between Ockham and Burleigh. Ockham openly qualifies this opinion of the realists or the 'communiter loquentium' as a falsehood.89 Burleigh went immediately over to the counterattack. He wrote: Some criticize the formulation: Simple supposition is given when a term stands for that which it signifies; for they criticize the older ones and say that this is false and impossible. They rather say that personal supposition is given when a term stands for that which it signifies or for the things signified. But that simple supposition is given, when a term stands for the intention or the intentions of the mind . . . But without any doubt this is quite irreasonably said . . .40 38Cfr. Javellus, op. cit., fol. 172b, (a Thomist); a very instructive explanation is given by the Scotist, Johannes de Magistris, Summularum Petri Hispani glosulae exactae ad mentem Doctoris Subtuis, Tr. VII, Venice, 1490. 39Cfr. Summa logicae, p. I, c. 64; p. 178, 33 rss. 40Burleigh, De puritate artis logicae, Tractatus longior, Tr. I, p. I, c 3; ed. p. 7, 5 ss." @default.
- W2085173615 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W2085173615 creator A5060541610 @default.
- W2085173615 date "1958-01-01" @default.
- W2085173615 modified "2023-10-17" @default.
- W2085173615 title "A Medieval Theory of Supposition" @default.
- W2085173615 cites W1485422928 @default.
- W2085173615 cites W2046477528 @default.
- W2085173615 cites W3143046807 @default.
- W2085173615 cites W590372723 @default.
- W2085173615 doi "https://doi.org/10.1353/frc.1958.0006" @default.
- W2085173615 hasPublicationYear "1958" @default.
- W2085173615 type Work @default.
- W2085173615 sameAs 2085173615 @default.
- W2085173615 citedByCount "5" @default.
- W2085173615 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2085173615 hasAuthorship W2085173615A5060541610 @default.
- W2085173615 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W2085173615 hasConceptScore W2085173615C138885662 @default.
- W2085173615 hasIssue "3-4" @default.
- W2085173615 hasLocation W20851736151 @default.
- W2085173615 hasOpenAccess W2085173615 @default.
- W2085173615 hasPrimaryLocation W20851736151 @default.
- W2085173615 hasRelatedWork W1030430500 @default.
- W2085173615 hasRelatedWork W1494974852 @default.
- W2085173615 hasRelatedWork W2227612306 @default.
- W2085173615 hasRelatedWork W2748952813 @default.
- W2085173615 hasRelatedWork W2803307177 @default.
- W2085173615 hasRelatedWork W2899084033 @default.
- W2085173615 hasRelatedWork W2912137438 @default.
- W2085173615 hasRelatedWork W3166162583 @default.
- W2085173615 hasRelatedWork W3214635344 @default.
- W2085173615 hasRelatedWork W2346533055 @default.
- W2085173615 hasVolume "18" @default.
- W2085173615 isParatext "false" @default.
- W2085173615 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W2085173615 magId "2085173615" @default.
- W2085173615 workType "article" @default.