Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2161423430> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 59 of
59
with 100 items per page.
- W2161423430 endingPage "84" @default.
- W2161423430 startingPage "47" @default.
- W2161423430 abstract "It is well known that Maimonides rejects the Kalam argument for the existence of God because it assumes the temporal creation of the world, a premise for which he says there is no “cogent demonstration (burhan qat'i) except among those who do not know the difference between demonstration, dialectics, and sophistic argument.”Moses Maimonides, The Guide of the Perplexed, trans. Shlomo Pines (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963), I:71:180. All references are to this translation; parenthetic in-text references are to part, chapter, and page. By contrast, he claims to establish belief in the existence of God “through a demonstrative method as to which there is no disagreement in any respect” (I:71:182). Taken at his word, Maimonides’ proofs for the existence of the deity, like Aquinas’s five ways, have traditionally been read as models of medieval natural theology: of the power of human reason to independently establish revealed truth. In recent years, however, the same demonstrations have assumed a second kind of significance. For scholars, like myself, who argue that Maimonides holds severe views about the limitations of human knowledge of divine science and metaphysics, these demonstrations are the strongest conceivable counterevidence.The locus classicus for this view is Shlomo Pines, “The Limitations of Human Knowledge According to Al-Farabi, Ibn Bajja, and Maimonides,” in Studies in Medieval Jewish History and Literature, ed. I Twersky, 3 vols. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979), I:82–109. See also his “Les Limites de la Métaphysique selon Al-Farabi, ibn Bajja et Maimonide; Sources et Antitheses de ces Doctrines chez Alexandre d’Aphrodise et Chez Themistius,” Miscellanea Mediaevalia 13 (1981): 211–25; “Dieu et L’Etre Selon Maimonide: Exégese d’Exode 3,14 et doctrine connexe,” in Celui qui est: Interprétations juives et chrétiennes d’Exode 3, 14, ed. A. de Libera et E. Zum Brunn (Paris: Les Editions du Cerf [Collection “Patrimoines”], 1986), 15–24; and “The Relation between Maimonides’ Halakhic and non-Halakhic Works,” in Maimonides and Philosophy, ed., S. Pines and Y. Yovel (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1987). Pines concludes, on the basis of the limitations of the intellect with respect to knowledge of metaphysics, that Maimonides, like Kant, gives priority to the practical over the theoretical. For arguments drawing different ‘skeptical’ conclusions, see my “Maimonides in the Skeptical Tradition,” ms.; “Maimonides on the Growth of Knowledge and the Limitations of the Intellect,” to appear in Tony Levy, ed., Maimonide: Traditions philosophiques et scientifiques médievales arabe, hébraique, latine; “Logical Syntax as a Key to a Secret of the Guide of the Perplexed,” (in Heb.), Iyyun 38 (1989): 137–66; “Maimonides on Language and the Science of Language,” in Maimonides and the Sciences, ed., H. Levine and R. Cohen (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2000), pp. 173–226; and The Matter and Form of Maimonides’ Guide (forthcoming). If Maimonides really held that humans cannot apprehend metaphysical truths about the deity, how could he have demonstrated (or even thought he could demonstrate) the existence of God? If he does demonstrate it, then humans evidently do have knowledge of metaphysics. As one distinguished scholar has recently protested, it is nothing less than “perverse” to interpret Maimonides as “meaning that the existence of God is unknowable when he in fact prides himself on having demonstrated the existence of God in four different ways.”Herbert A. Davidson, “Maimonides on Metaphysical Knowledge,” Maimonidean Studies 3 (1992–1993): 49–103, 86. See also Alfred L. Ivry, “The Logical and Scientific Premises of Maimonides’ Thought,” in Perspectives on Jewish Thought and Mysticism, ed. Alfred L. Ivry, Elliot R. Wolfson, and Allan Arkush (Amsterdam: Harwood Publishers, 1998), pp. 63–97, 70." @default.
- W2161423430 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W2161423430 creator A5076998264 @default.
- W2161423430 date "2001-03-01" @default.
- W2161423430 modified "2023-10-13" @default.
- W2161423430 title "Maimonides’ Demonstrations: Principles and Practice" @default.
- W2161423430 doi "https://doi.org/10.1017/s1057060801101039" @default.
- W2161423430 hasPublicationYear "2001" @default.
- W2161423430 type Work @default.
- W2161423430 sameAs 2161423430 @default.
- W2161423430 citedByCount "19" @default.
- W2161423430 countsByYear W21614234302017 @default.
- W2161423430 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2161423430 hasAuthorship W2161423430A5076998264 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C126322002 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C13184196 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C182744844 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C18296254 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C27206212 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C2778023277 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C71924100 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C74916050 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C95457728 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConcept C98184364 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C111472728 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C126322002 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C13184196 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C138885662 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C182744844 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C18296254 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C27206212 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C2778023277 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C71924100 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C74916050 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C95457728 @default.
- W2161423430 hasConceptScore W2161423430C98184364 @default.
- W2161423430 hasIssue "1" @default.
- W2161423430 hasLocation W21614234301 @default.
- W2161423430 hasOpenAccess W2161423430 @default.
- W2161423430 hasPrimaryLocation W21614234301 @default.
- W2161423430 hasRelatedWork W2007493167 @default.
- W2161423430 hasRelatedWork W2115206405 @default.
- W2161423430 hasRelatedWork W2217578549 @default.
- W2161423430 hasRelatedWork W2369134659 @default.
- W2161423430 hasRelatedWork W2487798799 @default.
- W2161423430 hasRelatedWork W2778213078 @default.
- W2161423430 hasRelatedWork W2793004112 @default.
- W2161423430 hasRelatedWork W3161909777 @default.
- W2161423430 hasRelatedWork W4237844617 @default.
- W2161423430 hasRelatedWork W4252540304 @default.
- W2161423430 hasVolume "10" @default.
- W2161423430 isParatext "false" @default.
- W2161423430 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W2161423430 magId "2161423430" @default.
- W2161423430 workType "article" @default.