Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2329054938> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 68 of
68
with 100 items per page.
- W2329054938 endingPage "577" @default.
- W2329054938 startingPage "575" @default.
- W2329054938 abstract "~OOK REVIEWS 575 linking the two major parts of Kant's ethics and making sense of concerns, in the context of a whole life, that cannot in the final analysis be kept separate. Steven's work shows connection and development in Kant's statements on character where others have found only idiosyncracies and laughably quaint convictions. This is in part due to the fact that he discusses Kant in the context of the 18th-century debate over the formation of character. But it is also a result of a sensitive and insightful reading of Kant that allows for the first time a recognition of the full importance of honesty in Kant's theory of virtue. Because Stevens carefully places Kant's remarks on character in historical context, he is able to raise issues that point to new directions in Kant scholarship. Thomas Auxter University of Florida Jill V. Buroker. Space and Incongruence: The Origin ofKant's Idealism. Synthese Historical Library, vol. 21. Dordrecht, Boston, and London: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1981. Pp. 143. $31.5~. Through a partly exegetic and historical but mostly logical and theoretical reconstruction of Kant's thoughts, this study argues that Kant's apparently disjoint uses of incongruent counterparts to show that space is absolute 0768), a pure intuition (177o), transcendentally ideal, merely subjective, and not related to things in themselves (1783, 1786) were actually related uses of incongruent counterparts and indeed formed the cornerstone of Kant's transcendental idealism. The study is commendable for drawing attention to several of Kant's early works, for suggesting how certain aspects of his Leibnizian heritage were accepted, modified and/or rejected, and for critically evaluating several recent commentaries on the Kantian theory of space and sensibility. But the study gives an unsympathetic and oversimplified account of Leibniz's theory, ignores primary and secondary literature which is not in English translation, and in general is myopic in its effort to show that Kant's concern with incongruence was the determining factor of his transcendental idealism. The first two chapters compare Newton's absolute theory of space with the relational theory as discussed by Berkeley, Mach, and Leibniz. The introduction of Berkeley and Mach's theory is unnecessary since there is no subsequent use of the non-Leibnizian theory in this study. Buroker's examination of Kant's Regions m Space0768) in chapter 3 anachronously discusses Kant's concept of an incongruent counterpart in terms of n-dimensional, orientable, non-orientable, Euclidean, non-Euclidean, homogeneous , non-homogeneous, local, and global spaces, while simultaneously using the term space--the very meaning of which is the issue between the relationists and the absolutists--as if it were unambiguous; for example, the claim is made that it is a fact that space is only three-dimensional (p. 56). The author then argues through a comparison of recent commentaries by Lawrence Sklar, Graham Nerlich, and John Earman , but without citing either Kant or Leibniz, that the x768 argument is not decisive against Leibniz's relational theory, even though Kant thought that it was. Finally, 576 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 21 4 OCT t983 Buroker suggests that the real importance of Kant's Regions in Space was the awakening of Kant's epistemological concerns about space. The key to Kant's transition from metaphysical concerns in 1768 to epistemological concerns in the 177o Inaugural Dissertation and later, Buroker argues in Chapter 4, must have been Kant's reflection on Leibniz's theory of relations. Since the distinguishability of incongruent counterparts entailed that knowledge of space be given with, but not abstracted from, the perception of objects, and since we experience only one given space whose parts are extensively related within it, the representation of space must be through sensible intuition and not through the understanding. Consequently , in 177o Kant rejected Leibniz's view that sensations are merely confused concepts. Lewis W. Beck, in a work not cited by Buroker, has already shown that this same progression of Kant's thoughts was actually aimed at Wolff and Baumgarten's single-faculty theory of knowledge? Two interpretations by Adolf Griinbaum and Jonathan Bennett of Kant's use of incongruent counterparts are then criticized by Buroker..." @default.
- W2329054938 created "2016-06-24" @default.
- W2329054938 creator A5040176766 @default.
- W2329054938 date "1983-01-01" @default.
- W2329054938 modified "2023-10-17" @default.
- W2329054938 title "Space and Incongruence: The Origin of Kant's Idealism (review)" @default.
- W2329054938 cites W2046796533 @default.
- W2329054938 cites W2090652908 @default.
- W2329054938 doi "https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.1983.0101" @default.
- W2329054938 hasPublicationYear "1983" @default.
- W2329054938 type Work @default.
- W2329054938 sameAs 2329054938 @default.
- W2329054938 citedByCount "0" @default.
- W2329054938 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2329054938 hasAuthorship W2329054938A5040176766 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C166957645 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C17744445 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C188370112 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C196595271 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C199539241 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C2524010 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C27206212 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C2777239683 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C2778061430 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C2779343474 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C2780861071 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C33923547 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C517673595 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConcept C95457728 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C111472728 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C138885662 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C166957645 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C17744445 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C188370112 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C196595271 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C199539241 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C2524010 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C27206212 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C2777239683 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C2778061430 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C2779343474 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C2780861071 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C33923547 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C517673595 @default.
- W2329054938 hasConceptScore W2329054938C95457728 @default.
- W2329054938 hasIssue "4" @default.
- W2329054938 hasLocation W23290549381 @default.
- W2329054938 hasOpenAccess W2329054938 @default.
- W2329054938 hasPrimaryLocation W23290549381 @default.
- W2329054938 hasRelatedWork W131949630 @default.
- W2329054938 hasRelatedWork W2054258938 @default.
- W2329054938 hasRelatedWork W2128747134 @default.
- W2329054938 hasRelatedWork W2163105352 @default.
- W2329054938 hasRelatedWork W2267411702 @default.
- W2329054938 hasRelatedWork W2329805303 @default.
- W2329054938 hasRelatedWork W2811444628 @default.
- W2329054938 hasRelatedWork W2940062896 @default.
- W2329054938 hasRelatedWork W4238839429 @default.
- W2329054938 hasRelatedWork W3081785762 @default.
- W2329054938 hasVolume "21" @default.
- W2329054938 isParatext "false" @default.
- W2329054938 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W2329054938 magId "2329054938" @default.
- W2329054938 workType "article" @default.