Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2578702567> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 86 of
86
with 100 items per page.
- W2578702567 abstract "Pain as Enactive Perception: Applying Noe’s Theory of Perception Alice I. Kyburg (kyburg@uwosh.edu) Department of Philosophy, University of Wisconsin Oshkosh Oshkosh, WI 54901 USA Abstract Pain as “Active” Representation We begin with a view defended elsewhere that pain is a representation of tissue damage that is dependent on what one is doing. We extend this view by exploring a relation between pain and action inspired by Alva Noe’s theory of perception. We consider whether sensorimotor knowledge related to tissue damage plays a role in pain experience. We explore this possibility by considering various kinds of pain, including the pain of a thorn in one’s foot, that of a herniated disk, and the chronic pain that sometimes follows the healing of an injury. We find that there is a large class of pain for which the phenomenal experience could easily be informed by sensorimotor knowledge in much the way Noe claims it is for vision and other forms of perception. We also find that conceiving of pain in this way inspires new understanding of phantom limb pain and chronic pain. I support Tye’s representational account of pain, with the qualification that representations of tissue damage are dynamic and very likely to depend on the activities the subject is engaged in and the demands they place on his representational resources. To emphasize that actions influence how things are represented, I call this version of the representation account of pain the active representational account. The idea is that pain is, in several ways, like vision and other forms of perception: (1) there are special-purpose sensorimotor pairings that serve to reduce the subject’s representational load while facilitating specific actions and (2) the total representational load dedicated to representing tissue damage is a function of the other demands on a subject’s representational resources. 1 If one has stepped on a thorn the traditional representationist will say that one’s foot pain is the representation of damage to one’s foot by the thorn. The active representationalist will agree, but will emphasize that one’s foot pain may vary with the activity one is engaged in. If one is walking with a thorn in one’s foot one will have a pain that facilitates such walking. In this case the particular representation of tissue damage is part of a specialized sensorimotor pairing. If the subject lies down for a nap in the woods the pain will have a different phenomenal content – it will still be a representation of a foot injury, but it will lack the content necessary for walking. Consider the type of pain one often has when one is first injured. There is the initial “Ow!”, a sudden, intense, all encompassing pain. The content of this representation includes particular information about the injury, such as its location and whether it is, for instance, a burn, a stab, a cut, or a knock with a heavy object. The greater demand on representational resources comes from the urgent need to act (sometimes, even, the instinct to act) by, for example, withdrawing one’s limb from the heat source, stepping away from the poking stick, or just removing all stress from the injured limb. It is likely that the representation of tissue damage during this initial phase facilitates the carrying out of such defensive acts. Consider the initial pain of a thorn entering deeply into one’s foot. One experiences the sharp piercing pain, has a sudden and powerful urge to raise one’s foot and keep it up, and tries to do so. Nearly all unrelated thoughts and actions cease. Keywords: pain;perception;enactive perception;action Introduction Philosophical accounts of pain have covered a wide variety of theories. A recent theory by Colin Klein (2007) is that pain is an imperative, the content of which defines the quality of the experience. Michael Tye (1995, 2005) conceives of pain as a nonconceptual representation of tissue damage (or disruption). I have argued that these two accounts are much closer to each other than they at first appear and that the representationist account can be expanded to incorporate the strengths of the imperative account by acknowledging the role of action in determining how tissue damage is represented. In this paper I further develop this action-based representational account of pain by incorporating insights from (Noe, 2004) on active perception. In Section Two I describe the active representational account of pain, an expanded version of Tye’s representational account of pain, that explicitly incorporates the hypothesis that how pain is represented is influenced by the activities one is engaged in. In Section Three I present some aspects of Noe’s action-centered account of perception that have interesting applications to pain when pain is understood as a kind of perception. In Section Four I apply these ideas to the expanded representational account of pain presented in Section Two. In Section Five I consider how this augmented active representational account of pain fares with some of the more philosophically difficult cases of pain. See (Hayhoe & Ballard, 2005) and (Ballard et al., 1991)" @default.
- W2578702567 created "2017-01-26" @default.
- W2578702567 creator A5070553028 @default.
- W2578702567 date "2011-01-01" @default.
- W2578702567 modified "2023-09-27" @default.
- W2578702567 title "Pain as Enactive Perception: Applying Noe's Theory of Perception" @default.
- W2578702567 cites W1507577307 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W1579973461 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W1589088869 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W1632686212 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W1684415682 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W1971148724 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W1986832582 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W1988507408 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2012907756 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2034697219 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2040289549 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2055235515 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2064698198 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2090992897 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2136672018 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2147299944 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2277679676 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2397253692 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2475578069 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2477904143 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W254429973 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W2913703059 @default.
- W2578702567 cites W632970994 @default.
- W2578702567 hasPublicationYear "2011" @default.
- W2578702567 type Work @default.
- W2578702567 sameAs 2578702567 @default.
- W2578702567 citedByCount "0" @default.
- W2578702567 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2578702567 hasAuthorship W2578702567A5070553028 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C121332964 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C15744967 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C161191863 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C169760540 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C17744445 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C180747234 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C188147891 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C199539241 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C26760741 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C2776359362 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C2777855551 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C2780791683 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C2781118164 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C41008148 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C62520636 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConcept C94625758 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C121332964 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C15744967 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C161191863 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C169760540 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C17744445 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C180747234 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C188147891 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C199539241 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C26760741 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C2776359362 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C2777855551 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C2780791683 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C2781118164 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C41008148 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C62520636 @default.
- W2578702567 hasConceptScore W2578702567C94625758 @default.
- W2578702567 hasIssue "33" @default.
- W2578702567 hasLocation W25787025671 @default.
- W2578702567 hasOpenAccess W2578702567 @default.
- W2578702567 hasPrimaryLocation W25787025671 @default.
- W2578702567 hasRelatedWork W132866304 @default.
- W2578702567 hasRelatedWork W1501766705 @default.
- W2578702567 hasRelatedWork W1546968348 @default.
- W2578702567 hasRelatedWork W1976708444 @default.
- W2578702567 hasRelatedWork W2085294194 @default.
- W2578702567 hasRelatedWork W2126712075 @default.
- W2578702567 hasRelatedWork W2204057618 @default.
- W2578702567 hasRelatedWork W2904503210 @default.
- W2578702567 hasRelatedWork W2979321766 @default.
- W2578702567 hasRelatedWork W40191330 @default.
- W2578702567 hasVolume "33" @default.
- W2578702567 isParatext "false" @default.
- W2578702567 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W2578702567 magId "2578702567" @default.
- W2578702567 workType "article" @default.