Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2604964944> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 75 of
75
with 100 items per page.
- W2604964944 endingPage "298" @default.
- W2604964944 startingPage "270" @default.
- W2604964944 abstract "THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF DISCOMFORT: RICHARD RORTY AND PRAGMATISM 0 VER THE LAST twenty years, one of the most consistently incisive critics of traditional Anglo-American philosophy has been Richard Rorty. Few contemporary writers can match the vigor, breadth, and intelligence of his books and articles, even as few readers can accept the radicality of the views they express. Rorty disturbs and astonishes like spring weather. His pages mount like cumulus clouds in our intellectual sky, saturated by the past and promising (ambiguously) either to irrigate or to inundate the present fields of our culture. Almost everybody complains about him, but can anything be done? This essay is an attempt to come to grips with aat least part of Rorty's multi-faceted and troubling corpus. His diagnosis of the root problems of epistemology and their larger significance (or insignificance) for Western intellectual life is often brilliant, but I shall argue that his prescription for the future is unattractive. His uncompromising war on dogmatism is based on a rejection of conventional notions of objective truth and metaphysical comfort and is presented in the name of human freedom. It represents, however , a potentially disastrous kind of pragmatism which can be criticized on both theoretical and practical grounds. Of the two, the practical considerations may perhaps be the more telling. I. The Problems of Reading Rorty In Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Rorty evaluates modern philosophy's comon self-understanding.1 One as1 Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979). ~70 RICHARD RORTY AND PRAGMATISM 271 sumed occupation of the discipline, on his view, is the discovery of the foundations of knowledge and thus the validation or invalidation of specific claims to know made in such various fields as science, ethics, art, and religion. Philosophy can claim to take the measure of these other areas of intellectual life because it claims to understand the nature of the mind and its capacity for accurate representation of reality. Philosophy can claim to be foundational with respect to the rest of culture because it claims to encompass the rest of culture, because it claims to know better than science and religion, for instance, what communion with reality they can and cannot attain to. Or so many modern philosophers would (perhaps only implicitly) believe. Rorty suggests that this conception of philosophy stems largely from intellectual developments beginning in the 17th Century, and in this vein he isolates three key contributions: (1) Descartes's idea of the mind as a separate substance, the inner workings of which are uniquely knowable to itself; (2) Locke's idea that a theory of knowledge is both necessary and possible on the basis of an understanding of the mind and how it works; and (3) Kant's idea that philosophy both can and should provide other fields with overarching canons of reason by dissecting a priori the structure of reason itself. These three contributions to modern philosophy's self-image are interrelated but nonetheless distinguishable. Each played its own crucial part in suggesting a foundation for that discipline , philosophy, which claimed to be foundational for all others. Over against this common picture of philosophy and its proper labors stand Rorty's heroes: Wittgenstein, Heidegger , and Dewey. These three men agree, in Rorty's estimation , that the picture (common to Descartes, Locke, and Kant) of knowledge as needing certain foundations and of the mind as locus of privileged epistemic processes, needs to be abandoned. They agree that both epistemology and metaphysics can and should be set aside as possible disciplines 272 TIMOTHY P. JACKSON in the name of a therapeutic form of life and a postmodernist self-image.2 It is this deconstructive, therapeutic line that Rorty wishes to champion. Philosophy should no longer conceive of itself as underwriting links between the human mind and the objective world; we have no access to the objective world as it is in itself; so most of traditional epistemology is misguided. Rorty characterizes his efforts as more akin to moral surusion than rigorous argument, claiming that the epistemological positions with which he takes exception are immune to such argument but objectionable (or at least optional) even so..." @default.
- W2604964944 created "2017-04-14" @default.
- W2604964944 creator A5063410318 @default.
- W2604964944 date "1987-01-01" @default.
- W2604964944 modified "2023-10-17" @default.
- W2604964944 title "The Theory and Practice of Discomfort: Richard Rorty and Pragmatism" @default.
- W2604964944 cites W120589643 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W1500856906 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W1971403288 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W1972236383 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2002302458 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2007204292 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2011515246 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2012651859 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2030537900 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2064314226 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2085900077 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2147433814 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2159866583 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2262632229 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2321302015 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2323424741 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2327824640 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2478635762 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2481246094 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2597768409 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2734469012 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2773969979 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2796528567 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W2799451800 @default.
- W2604964944 cites W639787000 @default.
- W2604964944 doi "https://doi.org/10.1353/tho.1987.0031" @default.
- W2604964944 hasPublicationYear "1987" @default.
- W2604964944 type Work @default.
- W2604964944 sameAs 2604964944 @default.
- W2604964944 citedByCount "6" @default.
- W2604964944 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2604964944 hasAuthorship W2604964944A5063410318 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConcept C158573231 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConcept C182744844 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConcept C41895202 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConcept C522434184 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConcept C537492667 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConcept C554936623 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConceptScore W2604964944C111472728 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConceptScore W2604964944C138885662 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConceptScore W2604964944C158573231 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConceptScore W2604964944C182744844 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConceptScore W2604964944C41895202 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConceptScore W2604964944C522434184 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConceptScore W2604964944C537492667 @default.
- W2604964944 hasConceptScore W2604964944C554936623 @default.
- W2604964944 hasIssue "2" @default.
- W2604964944 hasLocation W26049649441 @default.
- W2604964944 hasOpenAccess W2604964944 @default.
- W2604964944 hasPrimaryLocation W26049649441 @default.
- W2604964944 hasRelatedWork W1699653520 @default.
- W2604964944 hasRelatedWork W2013210170 @default.
- W2604964944 hasRelatedWork W2282523473 @default.
- W2604964944 hasRelatedWork W2532925148 @default.
- W2604964944 hasRelatedWork W2592582432 @default.
- W2604964944 hasRelatedWork W2993218937 @default.
- W2604964944 hasRelatedWork W3081433947 @default.
- W2604964944 hasRelatedWork W3134833962 @default.
- W2604964944 hasRelatedWork W3164009093 @default.
- W2604964944 hasRelatedWork W4200435873 @default.
- W2604964944 hasVolume "51" @default.
- W2604964944 isParatext "false" @default.
- W2604964944 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W2604964944 magId "2604964944" @default.
- W2604964944 workType "article" @default.