Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W2982310382> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 55 of
55
with 100 items per page.
- W2982310382 abstract "More than 20 years ago, the pioneering pediatric ethicist William Bartholome1 wrote a fiery letter to the editor of this journal because he thought a recently published statement on pediatric assent, from the Committee on Bioethics of the American Academy of Pediatrics (AAP), showed insufficient respect for children.2 That AAP statement, like its 2016 update, asserts that pediatric assent should be solicited only when a child’s dissent will be honored.3,4 Bartholome1 objected that pediatricians should always solicit children’s assent and that they should acknowledge and apologize when they treat children over their objections even when they must do so to promote children’s best interests.We think Bartholome1 was right. In this brief commentary, we elaborate on his perspective about the moral value of pediatric assent, and we suggest improvements to the corresponding clinical guidance.The AAP grounds the moral value of pediatric assent by noting, “We are obliged to act out of fundamental respect for other persons by virtue of their personal autonomy.” But in drawing on the concept of autonomy, the AAP invokes too narrow a conception of respect. Indeed, the AAP acknowledges that many children “lack the agency required to be truly autonomous agents.”3 If respect is grounded on autonomy, and if autonomy is what enables preferences to be authoritative, then perhaps it would be disrespectful to solicit preferences in situations in which a child’s dissent will not be honored. However, respect is about more than autonomy. In keeping with Bartholome’s concerns, a broader conception of respect supports a more stable commitment to pediatric assent.Respect is something we owe to others as a way to demonstrate that we recognize them as persons rather than objects. Patients (including children) are persons even if they do not reason well, particularly if they have a kind of agency that is capable of expressing preferences.5,6 One way to respect persons is to acknowledge that their preferences matter, something that may require soliciting those preferences, even in cases in which it would be ethically wrong to give them what they prefer. This is because it is disrespectful, and perhaps even dehumanizing, to treat preference-expressing patients as mere bystanders or obstacles to their own care.Pediatricians are often permitted, and sometimes obligated, to treat children over their objections. Whether a child’s preferences should be overridden in a particular case depends, among other things, on the child’s capacity to reason, but the preferences of even young or cognitively impaired children always have some moral value. Because a child’s preferences always have moral weight, even when it is right to set them aside, treating a child over objection always creates a residual moral harm that can be recognized through apology. This view underscores the importance of respecting children as persons and it honors the moral complexity of pediatrics, in which actions that ultimately may be right can have morally regrettable aspects.At its core, pediatric assent is about soliciting children’s preferences about treatment, in both discrete encounters or longitudinal contexts, in which preferences may shift and evolve. Consider the following case.Dr G.S. is a pediatrician seeing 4-year-old M.M., whose mother brought him to the clinic to have an abscess in his axilla lanced after attempting to treat it with hot compresses. On seeing the needle for the local anesthetic, M.M. begins to cry. Dr G.S. asks, “You do not want the shots, do you?” and M.M. says, “No! Needles hurt!” Dr G.S. replies, “I know, but this little lump is an infection, and we need to get that pus out to keep you healthy. So, we have to do it.” M.M. begins flailing his arms and legs, and Dr G.S. indicates that his mother should restrain him. M.M. struggles and screams, “No, no!” Just before the injection, the doctor says, “I’m sorry about this buddy.” M.M.’s mother keeps him restrained while Dr G.S. incises the abscess, irrigates it, and packs the wound. Afterward, M.M. continues to sob quietly, but he seems content by the time he leaves the clinic.This may seem like an unremarkable scenario. But its routine nature obscures its ethical complexity and the subtle and important moral work of pediatricians, particularly in navigating between children’s best interest and demonstrating respect for their preferences.Many organizations and advocates in pediatric ethics contend that a child’s assent should not be solicited in cases of inevitable treatment.5 One implication is that a child may feel deceived if their solicited preferences are overridden. But there is little reason to think that solicitations of patient preferences, when done properly (as we presume Dr G.S. does), invite children to expect their preferences to be fulfilled. Indeed, it is common for pediatricians to be explicit about the limits of their ability to fulfill patients’ preferences, for example, when they promise confidentiality to child patients. Furthermore, it is often difficult or impossible to avoid soliciting children’s preferences because all children, even those who are young or severely impaired, often offer spontaneous expressions of their preferences. For example, M.M. objects to his treatment even before Dr G.S. can inquire about M.M.’s preferences. These sorts of interactions are common in pediatrics, and their prevalence may reflect a widespread clinical intuition about what it means to respect children and value their preferences in cases of inevitable treatment.Pediatricians can demonstrate respect for children in many ways, including disclosing appropriate information and maintaining respectful communication. However, the practice of pediatric assent is a particularly important mechanism for demonstrating respect because it encourages the child’s active engagement in their care. The AAP can strengthen its efforts to promote respect for children by encouraging pediatricians to solicit assent even in cases of inevitable treatment and to express regret for treatment over objection even when it is justified.In practice, many pediatricians solicit their patients’ assent and apologize if they cannot give children what they want. Even if these reflect mere habits of speech, they may indicate an important professional virtue: a disposition to treat patients with respect.7 At its best, soliciting the preferences of children represents a form of epistemic humility, an acknowledgment that there is at least some possibility that what the child patient says will have a meaningful impact on their care, even when we think the treatment decision is a foregone conclusion. And we suspect that pediatricians’ tendency to apologize for coercive treatment also reflects their desire to acknowledge the moral wrongs committed in the pursuit of what is ultimately the morally right thing to do. This echoes the wisdom in Bartholeme’s1 decades-old criticism: apologies demonstrate respect, and they are a means to honor a patient’s objection without making that objection authoritative. Such an apology is not a concession of moral failure or an expression of guilt but a recognition that a morally appropriate course of action can involve subsidiary moral wrongs. We advocate for efforts to strengthen AAP guidance on pediatric assent and recommend that pediatricians solicit children’s preferences whenever possible and that they apologize for justified instances of treatment over objection. Such additions to AAP policy would honor the moral complexity of pediatrics and strengthen the AAP’s longstanding commitment to respecting children." @default.
- W2982310382 created "2019-11-08" @default.
- W2982310382 creator A5014498841 @default.
- W2982310382 creator A5065338644 @default.
- W2982310382 creator A5073260112 @default.
- W2982310382 date "2019-11-01" @default.
- W2982310382 modified "2023-09-30" @default.
- W2982310382 title "Pediatric Assent and Treating Children Over Objection" @default.
- W2982310382 cites W1664820920 @default.
- W2982310382 cites W2506793933 @default.
- W2982310382 cites W2805975851 @default.
- W2982310382 cites W2915648995 @default.
- W2982310382 cites W4230704730 @default.
- W2982310382 cites W4231516653 @default.
- W2982310382 doi "https://doi.org/10.1542/peds.2019-0382" @default.
- W2982310382 hasPubMedId "https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/31666301" @default.
- W2982310382 hasPublicationYear "2019" @default.
- W2982310382 type Work @default.
- W2982310382 sameAs 2982310382 @default.
- W2982310382 citedByCount "7" @default.
- W2982310382 countsByYear W29823103822020 @default.
- W2982310382 countsByYear W29823103822021 @default.
- W2982310382 countsByYear W29823103822022 @default.
- W2982310382 countsByYear W29823103822023 @default.
- W2982310382 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W2982310382 hasAuthorship W2982310382A5014498841 @default.
- W2982310382 hasAuthorship W2982310382A5065338644 @default.
- W2982310382 hasAuthorship W2982310382A5073260112 @default.
- W2982310382 hasBestOaLocation W29823103821 @default.
- W2982310382 hasConcept C187212893 @default.
- W2982310382 hasConcept C512399662 @default.
- W2982310382 hasConcept C71924100 @default.
- W2982310382 hasConceptScore W2982310382C187212893 @default.
- W2982310382 hasConceptScore W2982310382C512399662 @default.
- W2982310382 hasConceptScore W2982310382C71924100 @default.
- W2982310382 hasIssue "5" @default.
- W2982310382 hasLocation W29823103821 @default.
- W2982310382 hasLocation W29823103822 @default.
- W2982310382 hasOpenAccess W2982310382 @default.
- W2982310382 hasPrimaryLocation W29823103821 @default.
- W2982310382 hasRelatedWork W1506200166 @default.
- W2982310382 hasRelatedWork W1995515455 @default.
- W2982310382 hasRelatedWork W2048182022 @default.
- W2982310382 hasRelatedWork W2080531066 @default.
- W2982310382 hasRelatedWork W2604872355 @default.
- W2982310382 hasRelatedWork W2748952813 @default.
- W2982310382 hasRelatedWork W2899084033 @default.
- W2982310382 hasRelatedWork W3031052312 @default.
- W2982310382 hasRelatedWork W3032375762 @default.
- W2982310382 hasRelatedWork W3108674512 @default.
- W2982310382 hasVolume "144" @default.
- W2982310382 isParatext "false" @default.
- W2982310382 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W2982310382 magId "2982310382" @default.
- W2982310382 workType "article" @default.