Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W3123490581> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 66 of
66
with 100 items per page.
- W3123490581 startingPage "657" @default.
- W3123490581 abstract "Fidelity to Law and the Moral Pluralism Premise LAWYERS AND FIDELITY TO LAW. By W. Bradley Wendel. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2010. 286 pages. $35.00. Bradley Wendel is a pioneer on the new frontier of theoretical legal ethics. Wendel follows the lead of William Simon in breaking from the long-dominant discourse of moral theory in legal ethics and moving legal ethics toward a jurisprudence of lawyering.1 Rather than pursuing the more traditional question of whether it is possible for good lawyers to be good persons, Wendel focuses our attention on it means to be a good lawyer. One of the core functions of law practice is the interpretation of law. Clients seek legal advice because they want to understand the law says and how the law constrains their choices. Because lawyers have the power to interpret and declare the law through legal advice, Wendel argues, they have a professional responsibility to interpret the law faithfully.2 Lawyers and Fidelity to Law is Wendel's exploration of it means for lawyers to fulfill this professional responsibility. Legal ethics, Wendel once wrote, must be 'normative all the way down,' with a theory of democracy justifying a theory of the function of law, which in turn justifies a conception of the lawyer's role.3 In Fidelity to Law, Wendel presents and defends such a comprehensive theory of lawyering with two interrelated arguments: a functional argument that law deserves respect because of its capacity to settle normative controversy in a morally pluralistic society and a normative argument that law deserves respect because democratic lawmaking processes respect the equality and dignity of citizens. This Review focuses on one of the links in the chain of Wendel's normative-allthe- way-down argument: his move from the premise of moral pluralism to his conclusion that the function of law is to settle normative controversy in society. I question Wendel's move on both practical and theoretical grounds. Practically, it is questionable that law has the capacity to settle moral controversy-at least the deepest kind of controversy that society is unable to settle as a result of reasonable moral pluralism. And that is important, because at the deepest level of Wendel's normative-all-the-way-down argument, law's capacity to do something for us that we cannot do for ourselves is the source of the respect that we owe the law.4 More importantly, I question whether, in a morally pluralistic society, we should want law to settle normative controversy. Wendel argues that we need to settle such controversies so that we can move on and organize our affairs despite our deep disagreement about values. I argue, however, that efforts to unsettle law need not be seen as a threat: the continual ebb and flow of normative controversy can be viewed as an incident of, rather than an impediment to, a free and just society. I. Wendel's Argument from the Moral Pluralism Premise Fidelity to Law reinterprets the traditional partisan, and morally neutral, role morality of lawyers, grounding legal ethics in both jurisprudential and political theory. True to Wendel's earlier work,5 Fidelity to Law neither condones lawyers' minimal technical adherence to the law governing lawyers nor simply refers lawyers to moral values for guidance. Although in the past Wendel has argued that legal-professional values are plural,6 he now centers his theory of legal ethics around a single overarching value: fidelity to law. Wendel reshapes lawyers' duty of partisanship around clients' legal entitlements-defined as what the law, properly interpreted, actually provides for a client7-rather than the zealous pursuit of a client's legal interests.8 And Wendel reinterprets lawyers' traditional duty of moral neutrality toward their clients' ends as respect for the authority of law even in the face of disagreement with its substantive justice.9 Wendel grounds legal ethics in a jurisprudence heavily influenced by H. …" @default.
- W3123490581 created "2021-02-01" @default.
- W3123490581 creator A5037086621 @default.
- W3123490581 date "2012-02-01" @default.
- W3123490581 modified "2023-09-26" @default.
- W3123490581 title "Fidelity to Law and the Moral Pluralism Premise" @default.
- W3123490581 hasPublicationYear "2012" @default.
- W3123490581 type Work @default.
- W3123490581 sameAs 3123490581 @default.
- W3123490581 citedByCount "0" @default.
- W3123490581 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W3123490581 hasAuthorship W3123490581A5037086621 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C144024400 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C170692843 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C17744445 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C181294204 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C199539241 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C2777421848 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C2778023277 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C44725695 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C503263630 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConcept C71043370 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C111472728 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C138885662 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C144024400 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C170692843 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C17744445 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C181294204 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C199539241 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C2777421848 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C2778023277 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C44725695 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C503263630 @default.
- W3123490581 hasConceptScore W3123490581C71043370 @default.
- W3123490581 hasIssue "3" @default.
- W3123490581 hasLocation W31234905811 @default.
- W3123490581 hasOpenAccess W3123490581 @default.
- W3123490581 hasPrimaryLocation W31234905811 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W1482760994 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W1486363670 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W1495548090 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W1543792342 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W1576374864 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W1579276151 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W1597633301 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W1600039216 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W171772615 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W2025474872 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W2197683763 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W2253971358 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W2518383583 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W2735289001 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W2736179648 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W3122970593 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W3123015535 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W3124200041 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W3142805592 @default.
- W3123490581 hasRelatedWork W72771416 @default.
- W3123490581 hasVolume "90" @default.
- W3123490581 isParatext "false" @default.
- W3123490581 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W3123490581 magId "3123490581" @default.
- W3123490581 workType "article" @default.