Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W3128015782> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 70 of
70
with 100 items per page.
- W3128015782 endingPage "2162" @default.
- W3128015782 startingPage "2161" @default.
- W3128015782 abstract "FOR RELATED ARTICLE, SEE PAGE 2165The COVID-19 pandemic has forced ethical questions that once served as mere thought experiments to be considered with newfound urgency. The unprecedented strain on our health care system has collapsed the gulf between theory and practice in bioethics, laying bare both the need for well-formed crisis response plans and the practical challenges to their sound implementation. FOR RELATED ARTICLE, SEE PAGE 2165 Against this backdrop, authors from opposing vantage points take up the important question of whether it is ethically permissible to unilaterally withdraw life-sustaining treatments (LST) for reallocation during crisis standards of care in these “Point-Counterpoint” essays1Bishop J.P. Eberl J.T. Point: Is it ethically permissible to unilaterally withdraw life-sustaining treatments during crisis standards of care? Yes.Chest. 2021; 159: 2165-2166Abstract Full Text Full Text PDF PubMed Scopus (6) Google Scholar,2Sulmasy D.P. Maldonado F. Counterpoint: Is it ethically permissible to unilaterally withdraw life-sustaining treatments for reallocation during crisis standards of care? No.Chest. 2021; 159: 2167-2169Abstract Full Text Full Text PDF PubMed Scopus (3) Google Scholar in this issue of CHEST. Through their thoughtful examination of the theories that should guide our practice, they highlight the ethical tensions this pandemic accentuates, and they help us to see where such tensions lay hidden in plain sight in our everyday practice. Jeffrey Bishop and Jason Eberl1Bishop J.P. Eberl J.T. Point: Is it ethically permissible to unilaterally withdraw life-sustaining treatments during crisis standards of care? Yes.Chest. 2021; 159: 2165-2166Abstract Full Text Full Text PDF PubMed Scopus (6) Google Scholar assume the “Pro” side of this debate, arguing that such unilateral withdrawal is permissible, providing certain conditions have been met. They ground their claim in the societal “state of exception” that the current pandemic has occasioned, arguing that the exigencies of COVID-19 create a crisis state within medicine that is analogous to wartime in military ethical theory.1Bishop J.P. Eberl J.T. Point: Is it ethically permissible to unilaterally withdraw life-sustaining treatments during crisis standards of care? Yes.Chest. 2021; 159: 2165-2166Abstract Full Text Full Text PDF PubMed Scopus (6) Google Scholar,3Eberl J.T. Ethics as usual? Unilateral withdrawal of treatment in a state of exception.Am J Bioethics. 2020; 20: 210-211Crossref PubMed Scopus (5) Google Scholar More specifically, the authors draw on Just War Theory (JWT), which recognizes a societal state of exception (namely war, after all peaceable alternatives have been exhausted) that makes possible certain actions that are typically impermissible (ie, combat) for purposes of proportionate societal good. JWT therefore can offer moral coherence to unilateral withdrawal of care during a health care crisis through maximizing societal benefit by enhancing the chance of survival for patients deemed less sick. While Bishop and Eberl1Bishop J.P. Eberl J.T. Point: Is it ethically permissible to unilaterally withdraw life-sustaining treatments during crisis standards of care? Yes.Chest. 2021; 159: 2165-2166Abstract Full Text Full Text PDF PubMed Scopus (6) Google Scholar,3Eberl J.T. Ethics as usual? Unilateral withdrawal of treatment in a state of exception.Am J Bioethics. 2020; 20: 210-211Crossref PubMed Scopus (5) Google Scholar ground their justification in JWT, Daniel Sulmasy and Fabien Maldonado2Sulmasy D.P. Maldonado F. Counterpoint: Is it ethically permissible to unilaterally withdraw life-sustaining treatments for reallocation during crisis standards of care? No.Chest. 2021; 159: 2167-2169Abstract Full Text Full Text PDF PubMed Scopus (3) Google Scholar base their argument against unilateral withdrawal on discrete critiques that, taken together, create a compelling case that such action ought not be permitted even when medical resources are exhausted.2Sulmasy D.P. Maldonado F. Counterpoint: Is it ethically permissible to unilaterally withdraw life-sustaining treatments for reallocation during crisis standards of care? No.Chest. 2021; 159: 2167-2169Abstract Full Text Full Text PDF PubMed Scopus (3) Google Scholar Their claim rests on five arguments: that reallocation is practically unrealistic; that it is wrong to remove life-sustaining treatment from those who may survive if such treatment is maintained; that the process of reallocation contravenes the fiduciary commitment of the physician to the patient; that such practices may disproportionately affect marginalized populations; and that the rule of double effect (an ethical theory closely related to JWT) cannot be invoked to justify removal of LST. On one level, these “Pro” and “Con” essays can be read as expositions on the theory behind and practice of appropriate actions during times of crisis, respectively. Bishop and Eberl1Bishop J.P. Eberl J.T. Point: Is it ethically permissible to unilaterally withdraw life-sustaining treatments during crisis standards of care? Yes.Chest. 2021; 159: 2165-2166Abstract Full Text Full Text PDF PubMed Scopus (6) Google Scholar,3Eberl J.T. Ethics as usual? Unilateral withdrawal of treatment in a state of exception.Am J Bioethics. 2020; 20: 210-211Crossref PubMed Scopus (5) Google Scholar mount a strong case for the prima facie permissibility of LST removal grounded in moral theory that has existed since antiquity, and Sulmasy and Maldonado2Sulmasy D.P. Maldonado F. Counterpoint: Is it ethically permissible to unilaterally withdraw life-sustaining treatments for reallocation during crisis standards of care? No.Chest. 2021; 159: 2167-2169Abstract Full Text Full Text PDF PubMed Scopus (3) Google Scholar thoroughly address the problems with practical application of this or any theory that would justify LST removal. However, this simplified reading neglects one of the central questions with which both sets of authors grapple: what is the nature of the physician’s commitment to the patient in front of her, and how might this change in the face of competitors for her care? As both sets of authors note, the physician’s fiduciary commitment to the individual patient is constitutive of the medical practice and overrides any competing societal claims that may vie for the physician’s time and care. But is this unqualified commitment still operative during times of crisis, when she may have a duty to others who may benefit more from LST? Put another way, if the patient-physician relationship serves as the foundation of medicine, does the “state of exception,” which introduces novel and pressing competitors for the physician’s life-sustaining care (ie, different prospective patients) mean she is no longer practicing medicine, so understood? The dilemma of unilateral LST removal brings this question into stark and uncomfortable relief, but if we pay attention we recognize that the tension between meeting the needs of this particular patient against competitors for time, resources, and energy are in fact commonplace in everyday clinical practice. Very often, the competition for our care of individual patients is not another patient, but rather the increasing burden of nonclinical responsibilities that persistently pull us away from the bedside. The question of LST removal for reallocation is, quite literally, of vital importance. And yet, it is a task of choosing between real goods; that is, between the ability of different individual patients to survive and to heal. Such choices between competing, irreconcilable goods are remarkably difficult—the ancient Greeks in fact referred to the genre of theater dedicated to dilemmas that depicted the necessary loss of a good as tragedy.4MacIntyre A. After Virtue. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, IN1981Google Scholar Yet worse than tragedy is when we feel repeatedly compelled by the systems in which we operate to choose less worthy objects of our time and care than the good of the patients in front of us. We see this in the resident who isolates himself in a workroom to write notes rather than visit with patients at the end of his shift, or when the primary care doctor fails to fully advocate for insurance coverage for her patient in the face of the hours of bureaucratic maneuvering this would entail. We may not feel the visceral discomfort of such choices because they have become so commonplace, or because the implications of the choices are not so clear as the death of one patient so that another may live. However, for clinicians, the day-to-day decisions can feel like death by a thousand cuts even as they lack the singular force of the question of LST removal during crisis. Bishop, Eberl, Sulmasy, and Maldonado provide clear and compelling arguments as to how we might bridge the gap between the theory and practice of reallocation of life-sustaining treatments during this (and any other) time of medical crisis. Regardless of whether we ultimately find this particular action permissible or impermissible, perhaps what is most important is that we learn to detect the moral dilemmas that subtly inhere in our everyday care for patients, where crises may be muted but still present. Rebuttal From Drs Bishop and EberlCHESTVol. 159Issue 6PreviewSulmasy and Maldonado1 offer compelling practical and substantive reasons why unilateral withdrawal of life-sustaining treatment (LST) under crisis standards of care (CSCs) is not permissible. First, they cite the impracticality of daily reassessing ventilated patients and a potential revolving door of reallocations in an already taxed ICU. However, routine daily prognostic assessment of all patients is standard regardless of whether reallocation is being considered. Prognosis is always dynamic and does not admit of mathematical precision. Full-Text PDF Rebuttal From Drs Sulmasy and MaldonadoCHESTVol. 159Issue 6PreviewWe argued against the unilateral withdrawal of life-sustaining treatments for reallocation on two grounds: theoretical, because we believe that such reallocation does not conform with widely accepted bioethical principles, and practical, in that implementation would be fraught with difficulties in the real world such that judgment errors and biased decisions would be unavoidable. Drs. Bishop and Eberl only address the former, and while we agree that strict utilitarian considerations are inadequate, we disagree with them on several points. Full-Text PDF COUNTERPOINT: Is It Ethically Permissible to Unilaterally Withdraw Life-Sustaining Treatments for Reallocation During Crisis Standards of Care? NoCHESTVol. 159Issue 6PreviewSome proposals for responding to the possibility of an overwhelming surge of patients during a crisis suggest that physicians ought, if necessary, to reallocate life-sustaining treatments (LSTs), such as ventilators, from patients who are already receiving treatment but have a lesser chance of survival to patients who have a greater chance of survival.1-3 We argue that such reallocation is practically unrealistic, unfair to the person being treated, and damaging to the patient-physician relationship, and that it could discourage the disabled, people of color, and members of other marginalized groups from seeking treatment. Full-Text PDF POINT: Is It Ethically Permissible to Unilaterally Withdraw Life-Sustaining Treatments During Crisis Standards of Care? YesCHESTVol. 159Issue 6PreviewAs one of us has argued,1 the COVID-19 pandemic has produced a “state of exception”2 in which ordinary social, ethical, and political norms, although still valid, may be applied differently in specific concrete circumstances. Full-Text PDF" @default.
- W3128015782 created "2021-02-15" @default.
- W3128015782 creator A5057872074 @default.
- W3128015782 creator A5083245035 @default.
- W3128015782 date "2021-06-01" @default.
- W3128015782 modified "2023-09-24" @default.
- W3128015782 title "COVID-19 and Unilateral Withdrawal of Life-Sustaining Treatments" @default.
- W3128015782 cites W3044314749 @default.
- W3128015782 cites W3127578494 @default.
- W3128015782 cites W3128283407 @default.
- W3128015782 doi "https://doi.org/10.1016/j.chest.2021.02.005" @default.
- W3128015782 hasPubMedCentralId "https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/7985653" @default.
- W3128015782 hasPubMedId "https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/33581098" @default.
- W3128015782 hasPublicationYear "2021" @default.
- W3128015782 type Work @default.
- W3128015782 sameAs 3128015782 @default.
- W3128015782 citedByCount "1" @default.
- W3128015782 countsByYear W31280157822022 @default.
- W3128015782 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W3128015782 hasAuthorship W3128015782A5057872074 @default.
- W3128015782 hasAuthorship W3128015782A5083245035 @default.
- W3128015782 hasBestOaLocation W31280157821 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C116675565 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C126322002 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C159047783 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C177713679 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C2777914695 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C2778137277 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C2779134260 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C2909376813 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C3006700255 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C3007834351 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C3008058167 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C524204448 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConcept C71924100 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C116675565 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C126322002 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C159047783 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C177713679 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C2777914695 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C2778137277 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C2779134260 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C2909376813 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C3006700255 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C3007834351 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C3008058167 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C524204448 @default.
- W3128015782 hasConceptScore W3128015782C71924100 @default.
- W3128015782 hasIssue "6" @default.
- W3128015782 hasLocation W31280157821 @default.
- W3128015782 hasLocation W31280157822 @default.
- W3128015782 hasOpenAccess W3128015782 @default.
- W3128015782 hasPrimaryLocation W31280157821 @default.
- W3128015782 hasRelatedWork W3003901880 @default.
- W3128015782 hasRelatedWork W3004511262 @default.
- W3128015782 hasRelatedWork W3006792870 @default.
- W3128015782 hasRelatedWork W3012050440 @default.
- W3128015782 hasRelatedWork W3015398437 @default.
- W3128015782 hasRelatedWork W3016424513 @default.
- W3128015782 hasRelatedWork W3017133013 @default.
- W3128015782 hasRelatedWork W3035910609 @default.
- W3128015782 hasRelatedWork W3048586506 @default.
- W3128015782 hasRelatedWork W3107077827 @default.
- W3128015782 hasVolume "159" @default.
- W3128015782 isParatext "false" @default.
- W3128015782 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W3128015782 magId "3128015782" @default.
- W3128015782 workType "article" @default.