Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W4366809447> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 58 of
58
with 100 items per page.
- W4366809447 endingPage "94" @default.
- W4366809447 startingPage "85" @default.
- W4366809447 abstract "Reviews 85 RUSSELL’S CONTRIBUTION TO PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE James Connelly Philosophy, Trent U. Peterborough, on k9l 1z6, Canada jamesconnelly@trentu.ca Graham Stevens. The Theory of Descriptions: Russell and the Philosophy of Language . Basingstoke, uk: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011. Pp. xiii, 197. isbn: 978-0230 -20116-3. £50; us$85. ver the past decade, Graham Stevens has built his reputation as a lucid, durable, and oftentimes ground-breaking historian of analytic philosophy. His latest book, entitled TheTheory of Descriptions: Russell and the Philosophy of Language, will only add to that burgeoning scholarly legacy. If it has not been established already, this book will doubtless cement Stevens’ place amongst the leading Russell scholars in the world today. It may very well herald Stevens ’ arrival on the scene as a noteworthy contributor to contemporary philosophy of language as well. The central goal of the book is “to bring the historical and purely philosophical analyses of [Russell’s] work into closer alignment” (p. 3). Stevens hopes to overcome a “striking disparity” (p. 2) in the ways that Russell’s contributions to the philosophy of language have been conceived by expositors of his philosophy, on the one hand, versus philosophers of language, on the other. In particular, though contemporary philosophers of language would tend to view Russell’s enormous contribution to that subject as being “undeniable” (p. 1), and to be “bewildered” (p. 94) by any suggestion to the contrary, expositors of Russell’s philosophy have nevertheless been at pains to emphasize that Russell “was not engaged in the philosophical study of language” (p. 2). As Stevens notes, this situation is especially puzzling since “these two groups [of scholars] overlap to a considerable extent” (p. 2). Stevens’ strategy for overcoming this disparity is two-pronged. First he aims to tackle, head on, the fallacious arguments of Monk,1 Dummett,2 and others, to the effect that Russell was not engaged in the philosophy of language. According to Stevens, such arguments have principally appealed to either (1) ______ 1 Ray Monk, “What Is Analytical Philosophy?”. 2 Michael Dummett, Frege: Philosophy of Language. l= 86 Reviews Russell’s dismissal of ordinary language philosophy, (2) his early, non-linguistic , conception of the nature of propositions, or (3) his view that natural language was inherently defective for philosophical purposes, and so called for replacement by a “logically perfect language”. In regards to (1), Stevens argues in a word that “[o]rdinary language philosophy has had its day” (p. 176). Over the past several decades, in other words, leading philosophers of language have come to agree with Russell in viewing ordinary language philosophy as “an outdated, and rather eccentric, relic of mid-twentieth century British philosophy” (ibid.).The classic Russell– Strawson debate over the question whether ordinary language lacks an exact logic3 has been settled decisively in Russell’s favour, as philosophers of language have transformed “the attempt to systematically specify the semantics of large regions of natural language” (ibid.) into a “central project” (ibid.). In regards to (2), moreover, Stevens notes that by this line of reasoning, absurdly, David Kaplan would not qualify as a philosopher of language since he “explicitly invokes the Russellian non-linguistic conception of a proposition as the conception appropriate for providing the content of properly context-situated indexical sentences” (p. 170). And, of course, Kaplan is not at all unique amongst contemporary philosophers of language in appealing to a Russellian conception of propositional content, as the examples of Nathan Salmon,4 Scott Soames,5 and many others show. In regards to (3), finally, Stevens argues that Russell’s dim view of natural language was grounded in his conception of logical form as non-linguistic, and that that conception, in turn, derives simply from the poverty of syntactic theory available to Russell, prior to the Chomskyian revolution in linguistics during the second half of the twentieth century. In light of the conceptual and analytic resources made available by this revolution , however, there exists “no insurmountable obstacle to assimilating Russell ’s notion of logical form to something akin to the modern notion of lf” (p. 172), where lf is conceived as one of four levels of syntactic representation within Chomsky’s Government and Binding Theory..." @default.
- W4366809447 created "2023-04-25" @default.
- W4366809447 creator A5053216827 @default.
- W4366809447 date "2013-06-01" @default.
- W4366809447 modified "2023-10-17" @default.
- W4366809447 title "Russell’s Contribution to Philosophy Of Language" @default.
- W4366809447 doi "https://doi.org/10.1353/rss.2013.0017" @default.
- W4366809447 hasPublicationYear "2013" @default.
- W4366809447 type Work @default.
- W4366809447 citedByCount "0" @default.
- W4366809447 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W4366809447 hasAuthorship W4366809447A5053216827 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C111472728 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C123556308 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C146153142 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C161191863 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C170143251 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C182744844 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C2777855551 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C2779313563 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C41008148 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C41895202 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C74916050 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConcept C95457728 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C111472728 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C123556308 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C138885662 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C146153142 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C161191863 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C170143251 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C182744844 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C2777855551 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C2779313563 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C41008148 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C41895202 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C74916050 @default.
- W4366809447 hasConceptScore W4366809447C95457728 @default.
- W4366809447 hasIssue "1" @default.
- W4366809447 hasLocation W43668094471 @default.
- W4366809447 hasOpenAccess W4366809447 @default.
- W4366809447 hasPrimaryLocation W43668094471 @default.
- W4366809447 hasRelatedWork W165728417 @default.
- W4366809447 hasRelatedWork W1972824772 @default.
- W4366809447 hasRelatedWork W1995613716 @default.
- W4366809447 hasRelatedWork W2049303392 @default.
- W4366809447 hasRelatedWork W3024919272 @default.
- W4366809447 hasRelatedWork W324945932 @default.
- W4366809447 hasRelatedWork W4231486799 @default.
- W4366809447 hasRelatedWork W4321482283 @default.
- W4366809447 hasRelatedWork W4360978698 @default.
- W4366809447 hasRelatedWork W559981179 @default.
- W4366809447 hasVolume "33" @default.
- W4366809447 isParatext "false" @default.
- W4366809447 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W4366809447 workType "article" @default.