Matches in SemOpenAlex for { <https://semopenalex.org/work/W4379804966> ?p ?o ?g. }
Showing items 1 to 62 of
62
with 100 items per page.
- W4379804966 endingPage "58" @default.
- W4379804966 startingPage "32" @default.
- W4379804966 abstract "Why Does the Law Want Us to Be Normal?Schmitt’s Institutionalism and the Critique of the Liberal Legal Order Mariano Croce (bio) and Andrea Salvatore (bio) With a greater or lesser degree of sympathy and approval, Carl Schmitt has always been a point of reference for the critics of the liberal state. The pitiless denunciation of (what he viewed as) liberals’ hypocritical faith in the balance of powers and the neutrality of state law characterizes his oeuvre as a whole, despite the frequent adjustments his thinking underwent throughout his life. In this article, however, we claim that there is a phase in Schmitt’s theoretical development that is as instructive and enlightening as it is underestimated by most Schmitt scholars. In this phase, which we believe to be central to the understanding of Schmitt’s overall conception of politics, law, and society, he unraveled many of the theoretical impasses that he had incurred and left unsolved in the previous texts. More specifically, we claim that, notwithstanding his execrable allegiance to the Nazi regime, in the 1930s Schmitt set forth a thought-provoking institutional theory of law that allowed him to make his critique of liberalism deeper and more effective. In the first section of this article we scrutinize the reasons why Schmitt moved from his well-known decisionist paradigm to an institutional conception of law. In doing so, we cast light on the renewed role of normality in his legal theorizing and the way it is key to the existence of legal norms. In the second section we pin down Schmitt’s conception of the nature of norms vis-à-vis his polemic targets, normativism and legal positivism, to highlight the gist of his critique of the liberal legal order. On the basis of this, we contend that Schmitt’s institutionalist critique offers precious insights into the nature of the way law works on social reality. To vindicate this claim, in the third section we juxtapose his view with François Ewald’s Foucauldian view of norms to pinpoint interesting convergences in their critical analyses [End Page 32] on how norms serve as standards carrying out both cognitive and practical tasks. To show the import of our analysis, we bring Schmitt’s institutionalism to bear on the topical phenomenon of homonormativity, or rather, the normalizing effect of legal recognition on same-sex sexualities. In doing so, our goal is to show that Schmitt’s understanding of the foundational role of normality and its relation to the production of legal norms reveals something relevant to the nature of the legal order of liberal regimes, and in particular on the way these regimes try to conceal their selective and exclusionary activity with recourse to the claimed neutrality of state legal rules. The objective of this article, therefore, is twofold. On the one hand, it aspires to offer a novel contribution to the interpretation of Schmitt, well beyond a deep-seated reading that draws on his texts of the 1920s. On the other hand, we seek to do so in such a way that this analysis may help us decipher the ambiguous transitions of our time, where unquestionable progressions (such as the gradual accommodation of once-despised forms of kinship and sexuality) are accompanied by (barely visible) processes of exclusion, often disguised by the rhetoric of rights and equality. BEYOND DECISIONISM: SCHMITT’S INSTITUTIONAL TURN The identification of Schmitt’s theory with what is labeled “decisionism” is widely regarded as a platitude, if not a truism. Consequently, Schmitt is generally considered as the outstanding theorist of the notion of exception and its relevance for legal and political thought. According to this interpretation, the concept of exception lies at the heart of his theoretical framework as a whole and is the dominant element in the dialectical relationship between normality and exception. Based on this mainstream interpretation, normality is but the conceptual backdrop that allows the exception to emerge as the element that gives life to the legal order. Nevertheless, this can be considered a tenable account of Schmitt’s theoretical view only as long as one refers to the texts he published in the 1920s—that is, the period usually labeled his “decisionist phase..." @default.
- W4379804966 created "2023-06-09" @default.
- W4379804966 creator A5067598364 @default.
- W4379804966 creator A5084502556 @default.
- W4379804966 date "2016-01-01" @default.
- W4379804966 modified "2023-09-23" @default.
- W4379804966 title "Why Does the Law Want Us to Be Normal?: Schmitt’s Institutionalism and the Critique of the Liberal Legal Order" @default.
- W4379804966 doi "https://doi.org/10.1353/cul.2016.a631373" @default.
- W4379804966 hasPublicationYear "2016" @default.
- W4379804966 type Work @default.
- W4379804966 citedByCount "0" @default.
- W4379804966 crossrefType "journal-article" @default.
- W4379804966 hasAuthorship W4379804966A5067598364 @default.
- W4379804966 hasAuthorship W4379804966A5084502556 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C10138342 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C11413529 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C138885662 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C144024400 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C162324750 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C17744445 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C182306322 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C190253527 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C199539241 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C2779581858 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C41008148 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C48103436 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C547727832 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConcept C94625758 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C10138342 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C11413529 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C138885662 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C144024400 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C162324750 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C17744445 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C182306322 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C190253527 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C199539241 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C2779581858 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C41008148 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C48103436 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C547727832 @default.
- W4379804966 hasConceptScore W4379804966C94625758 @default.
- W4379804966 hasIssue "1" @default.
- W4379804966 hasLocation W43798049661 @default.
- W4379804966 hasOpenAccess W4379804966 @default.
- W4379804966 hasPrimaryLocation W43798049661 @default.
- W4379804966 hasRelatedWork W2006085426 @default.
- W4379804966 hasRelatedWork W2014338787 @default.
- W4379804966 hasRelatedWork W2136126962 @default.
- W4379804966 hasRelatedWork W2152225400 @default.
- W4379804966 hasRelatedWork W2494003565 @default.
- W4379804966 hasRelatedWork W2498021866 @default.
- W4379804966 hasRelatedWork W2748952813 @default.
- W4379804966 hasRelatedWork W2899084033 @default.
- W4379804966 hasRelatedWork W3081371213 @default.
- W4379804966 hasRelatedWork W4248377518 @default.
- W4379804966 hasVolume "93" @default.
- W4379804966 isParatext "false" @default.
- W4379804966 isRetracted "false" @default.
- W4379804966 workType "article" @default.